1,511
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Research Article

Reinterpreting “genetic identity” in the regulatory and ethical context of heritable genome editing

ORCID Icon, &
Pages 406-424 | Received 08 Jan 2020, Accepted 19 May 2021, Published online: 15 Jun 2021

Abstract

Heritable genome editing (HGE) is prohibited by several international conventions for a number of reasons, including the protection of “genetic identity.” This article provides a conceptual analysis of the concept of “genetic identity” and offers normative reflections as to how it should be interpreted in the context of HGE. In particular, this article examines the purported right to retain “genetic identity” and the right-to-know “genetic identity” in order to explore the possible implications of these understandings on the debate concerning HGE on nuclear genome. We argue that a right to retain “genetic identity,” that is a right to an untampered genome, is unlikely to be plausibly established if the current international provisions are used as the basis for governing the use of HGE, due to both conceptual and practical ambiguities. We note that the international framework may be more nuanced if it directly engages with what it means to “preserve humanity.” Furthermore, drawing on the existing literature on identity formation, we argue that “genetic identity” based on a narrative-based understanding of identity should be given more weight in the context of HGE because it better safeguards the interests of the children born via the technology, should the technology be legalized for clinical use.

1. Introduction

Human heritable genome editing (HGE) involves germline modification where modifications are made on the germ cells (sperms or eggs) or early human embryos. In contrast to somatic genome editing (that is modification of genes of a particular, existing patient), the technique has wider-reaching consequences that extend far beyond the individual to impact upon future generations. It is partly for this reason that HGE is regarded as far less ethically acceptable than somatic genome editing (NCB Citation2016a), and why its use for human reproduction is currently subject to an international prohibition (Araki and Ishii Citation2014). Although the acceptable safety level for its clinical use has yet to be reached, the introduction of CRISPR-Cas9 (see, e.g. NCB Citation2016b for a summary on CRISPR-Cas9) signifies that there is now a tool which is able to target and edit genes more efficiently with high precision; the simplicity of the technique also leads to fairly low cost (Berkeley News, July 23, Citation2015). Such developments therefore demand a more detailed regulatory framework (Turkmendag and Murphy Citation2019) that can accommodate and address the broader ethical concerns. This demand has even greater urgency following the news that the world’s first genetically modified twins have been created by Chinese scientist He JiankuiFootnote1 amid the international prohibition on HGE (The Guardian, November 26, Citation2018). Despite the ongoing controversy about HGE, there seems to be a shift of attitude towards the overall acceptance of the technology, especially when it is positioned within a “therapeutic”Footnote2 path. For instance, acknowledging that there are still gaps in the overall safety of HGE, the recent report by National Academy of Sciences (NAS Citation2020, 1 & 3) suggests that HGE could constitute “an important option for prospective parents with a known risk of transmitting a genetic disease to have a genetically-related child without that disease” and recommends, inter alia, that if HGE were to be introduced into clinical settings, it should be “limited to serious monogenic diseases.” In the UK, it is “within a framing of reproductive choice and disease prevention” that the mitochondrial replacement technique (“MRT”)Footnote3 has been extensively debated and eventually introduced into clinics for women with mitochondrial disease who want a genetically related, healthy child (Dimond and Stephens Citation2018, 5). Therefore, legalization of new technologies, including HGE, may distant itself from the wider ethico-legal debates. Nonetheless, there is a need to revisit the fundamental concepts that have informed our legal thinking on this issue.

There has been a breadth of socio-legal literature on the impacts of genetics on “identity”: for instance, how genetic knowledge offers a new way to understand oneself in terms of prognosis, prevention and treatment of disease (Tutton Citation2014); and how genetics might contribute to the conceptualization of “identity” of a particular group (Bliss Citation2013). Noting that there are a variety of meanings associated with the concept of “genetic identity” (Goekoop et al. Citation2020) but yet a lack of detailed analysis as to what it means and how it should be understood in the context of HGE, this article thus takes up two tasks. First, it provides a conceptual analysis of “genetic identity” with a focus on the international and UK perspectives. Second, it offers normative insights into the existing debate of HGE with regards to the interpretations of “genetic identity,” drawing upon the literature from law, bioethics and social science. Unpacking the concept is essential, particularly in light of prior experience in the UK regulation of related technologies, for instance, MRT, which has shown that “genetic identity” can be easily manipulated to serve the ends of different interest groups. In this article, we map the conceptualization of “genetic identity” onto two questions: (1) whether and to what extent the international provisions that prohibit HGE are effective in regulating this area; and (2) if HGE is proven safe and its clinical use becomes legal, how can we protect the interests of the resultant children who may be born as a result of HGE. In regard to (1), we examine a purported right to retain “genetic identity”; while for (2), we explore a right-to-know “genetic identity.” We first argue that the “genetic identity” which the international provisions seek to protect in the context of genome editing does not connote having a right to retain a genuine “genetic identity” (an untampered genome) but rather, a protection of human (species) identity which need not involve a total ban on modifying the human genome. We therefore recommend that focus is shifted to questions such as what should protection of human (species) identity entail in the context of HGE. Secondly, we suggest that rather than protecting “genetic” identity, the focus should be shifted towards protecting a narrative-based understanding of (genetic) identity. We argue that the existing regulations that protect a child’s right-to-know his/her genetic origins (in the context of third party conception) can provide useful insights to build a safeguard for the prospective children born via the procedure. A legal right-to-know would encourage the responsible use of technology as it would give more accountability to the third parties who regulate or facilitate the use of HGE. It would also allow resultant individuals from HGE to understand their medical background and make informed decisions about their health (including reproductive decisions as the genetic modifications they were subject to can be passed on to next generations) during their life course.

2. A right to retain “genetic identity”

We begin by exploring one of the key interests which underpins the current prohibition in international law of germline modification: the protection of “genetic identity” (Boussard Citation2009). This section focuses on how “genetic identity” is interpreted in the international provisions by analyzing the claim for a right to retain “genetic identity” since the latter has been frequently raised in the academic literature as an opposing argument against the use of HGE (Nolan Citation1991, 614; Holtug Citation1998; Baylis Citation2013, 534). This analysis is needed because there is currently a lack of detailed examination of such a notion and the plausibility to rely on such a claim to justify the legality and ethicality of HGE thus remains vague.

This notion of “genetic identity” arguably stemmed from the recommendation made by the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe (“PACE”) in Citation1982 where, in relation to genetic engineering, the PACE recommended that there might be a “right to inherit a genetic pattern which has not been artificially changed.” Article 13 of the 1997 Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine (“Oviedo Convention”) – the first legally binding international instrument to highlight the collective interests of human beings in the context of biomedical innovations – also provides that “(a)n intervention seeking to modify the human genome may only be undertaken (…) if its aim is not to introduce any modification in the genome of any descendants.” On its literal interpretation, any form of HGE is thus prohibited because the modified effects would, in fact, be passed on to descendants. The claim for a right to retain a genuine “genetic identity,” where “genuine” means without any intentional interference, hence connotes the idea that the human genome should not be intentionally manipulated (for example, via HGE). This view engenders a narrow interpretation whereby it only includes germline modification targeted at germ cells or early human embryos but excludes accidental germline effects from somatic genome editing (Parens Citation1995, 175).

The right to retain a genuine genetic identity appears to be based on two possible grounds: (1) human genomes should be protected because they are the common heritage of humankind; and/or (2) the intentional alteration of human genomes is contrary to human dignity. This is seen in the UNESCO’s Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights 1997 (the “1997 Declaration” – the first international legal and ethical framework to regulate the activities relating to the human genome) where, in the first Article, it declares that “the human genome underlies the fundamental unity of all members of the human family, as well as the recognition of their inherent dignity and diversity. In a symbolic sense, it is the heritage of humanity.”

2.1. Human genome as the “common heritage of humanity”

Reading the Article by itself, it is unclear what it means to view human genome as a common heritage of humanity. Referring to Agius’ work (Citation1998, 75), it is arguable that the human genetic system is part of the common heritage of humankind due to the heritable effects of genes in which the genes are passed down from one generation to the other. This genetic heritage belongs to all human beings and it goes beyond “national or temporal boundaries” and is “the biological heritage of the entire human species” (Agius Citation1998, 76). Nonetheless, the applicability of the common heritage view to human genomes is disputable: it has been suggested that there is no “germline” in human species in the genealogical sense (Juengst Citation1998, 87)Footnote4 and that it is hard to identify one single “thing” as the human genome due to “genetic variations” in which every individual owns a different set of genes (Resnik Citation2005, 200).

Even if we set aside the scientific viewpoint, applying the concept of common heritage to the human genome, particularly into the context of HGE, raises other concerns. It is pointed out that the idea of the “common heritage of humankind” was first developed within a different context in relation to the international sea and outer space (Primc Citation2020, 42). The common heritage idea in such contexts deals not with ownership but the uses of the designated area for the good of humankind, to serve the common interest of people everywhere (Buxton Citation2004, 692). Hence, it is not entirely clear if this principle can be applied to the legality or ethical acceptability of germline editing. Primc (Citation2020, 43) observes that the common heritage idea does not provide an answer to the ethical permissibility of germline modification, if it is interpreted as giving the people or nations equal property interests in a territory or resource (Ossorio Citation2007, 427–428). In a similar vein, Hey (Citation2014, 264) opines that the common heritage of humankind which aims to serve human interests may be fit to address “how benefits and burdens are to be shared from beneficial uses of the human genome and human genetic databases” but, it does not fit with other concerns, such as what it means to be “human” in a collective sense. The latter seems to be a more relevant concern, or even fundamental to the HGE debate, especially when dealing with the question of the morality of HGE.

Therefore, instead of focusing on property rights, some scholars including Ossorio (Citation2007, 430) point to a so-called “common heritage duties doctrine” in which it “articulates a special interest of all people in certain cultural or natural objects and a duty to help preserve them.” Primc (Citation2020, 44) argues that this understanding is a more promising one for the opponents of germline manipulation because it implies a duty to preserve the human genome. This duty, if understood with the right to an unaltered genome, may stipulate that there should be no intervention on the human genome by any technical concerns (Primc Citation2020, 44). Unfortunately, further problems remain with the “duty to preserve human genome.”

First, the idea of “protection of human genome” is problematic as it connotes genetic determinismFootnote5 – an idea which has consistently been rejected by the Legal Commission of the International Bioethics Committee of UNESCO (“the Committee”) (Division of the Ethics of Science and Technology Citation1999, 3, 62, 68, 75), leading to an eventual inclusion of a provision to condemn the notion of genetic determinism in the 1997 Declaration (Article 3). In the preparatory work of the 1997 Declaration, it is also emphasized that a right to respect one’s genetic heritage (that is not to be discriminated against) should not be seen as equivalent to the sanctity or inviolability of human genome (Division of the Ethics of Science and Technology Citation1999, 71). The Committee clarifies that the purpose of the Declaration is to “ensure the protection of the human genome against all forms of experimentation or use that are incompatible with respect for human dignity” and that “the purpose of protecting the human genome is to safeguard the integrity of the human species” (Division of the Ethics of Science and Technology Citation1999, 62). All these suggest that a duty to preserve the human genome need not lead to an outright ban on HGE, as long as it is used in accordance with “respect for human dignity” and “integrity of the human species” (discussed in more detail below).

Secondly, if the duty to preserve the human genome is based on safety concerns, arguably a right to a genuine genetic identity is only a provisional right because it can only sustain until the safety concern is resolved (Primc Citation2020, 44). The Committee clearly stated that the prohibition on germline editing at the time of drafting the 1997 Declaration is due to the state of scientific knowledge at that time (Division of the Ethics of Science and Technology Citation1999, 62). This is also demonstrated in the Oviedo Convention which allows amendment of the provisions (see Article 32). Consequently, a right to non-modified genomes is at best temporary and can be lifted when the technology is proven safe and effective enough. Clearly, the support in favor of this right is not as strong as first claimed in 1982, leaving such a duty to preserve the human genome vague or even redundant. It is notable that even when the PACE suggested the “right to inherit a genetic pattern which has not been artificially changed” be included as an aspect of human rights back in 1982, this purported right has not been included in the human rights provisions to date.

Hence, even if it is agreed that the human genome is a common heritage, it is questionable whether this view would constitute a right to retain a genuine genetic identity. One possible remedy for this situation is to adopt what Resnik (Citation2005) has suggested, albeit in a patenting human genome context, that there should be a symbolic interpretation (instead of literal interpretation) of common heritage. UNESCO itself has stressed this symbolic sense in the first Article. Looking at the preparatory work, it may be emphasized that the purpose of including the idea that human genome is a common heritage as a symbolic sense is not to completely prohibit HGE but “to underline the fact that research on the human genome and the applications that flow therefrom entail the responsibility of humanity as a whole, in the interest of present and future generations” (Division of the Ethics of Science and Technology Citation1999, 3). Therefore, it can be concluded that genome editing, including HGE warrants considerable precaution regarding its clinical implementation and must be examined on its own merits to determine its legality and morality.

2.2. Human genome and human dignity

Another possible way to defend a right to a genuine genetic identity is through the concept of human dignity. Article 24 of the 1997 Declaration indicates that HGE is a practice that could be contrary to human dignity. This suggests that attempts to intervene with the germ cells may, but not necessarily, be considered as contrary to human dignity. Agreeing with this, Krekora-Zajac (Citation2020, 3) points out that the position implied by Article 24 is different from Article 11 which clearly forbids reproductive cloning on the ground that it is contrary to human dignity. Hence, it is argued that the wording of the 1997 Declaration suggests that certain form of genetic intervention before birth may be acceptable and need not be a threat to human dignity or humanity (Krekora-Zajac Citation2020, 3).

How the concept of human dignity should be interpreted in the context of HGE remains ambiguous. Arguably, dignity, from the international perspective of protection of human species, is something that is inherent to human beings. This indicates that there is “an unconditional worth that everyone possesses by virtue of being human” deserving respect (Andorno Citation2011; Fukuyama Citation2002). If we agree on the intrinsic value of dignity, the concept of human dignity, understood in this way, cannot ground the possible right of an untampered genome because it would imply a counter-intuition that those born as a result of such technique are somehow less “dignified” (or afforded less dignity) than those who are not. Nonetheless, the concept of human dignity continues to gain traction in the HGE debate. In the updated statement by UNESCO concerning genome editing in 2015, it is stated that HGE would “jeopardise the inherent and therefore equal dignity of all human beings.” This statement seems to go against the view of dignity as an “unconditional worth” in which every human being, including those born genetically modified before birth, should be treated as having the same dignity as any other human being.

We argue that one possible interpretation of “human dignity” which is more plausible may be that HGE should only be carried out (if proven safe and effective) in a way that does not involve instrumentalization of the resultant individuals (Van Assche and Sterckx Citation2014, 278). Andorno (Citation2009, 228) rightly warns that people should not be treated as research tools and that scientific advancement is not an end in itself but merely a way to improve people’s welfare. Scientist He Jiankui’s experiment, which involved editing of the so-called CCR5 genes in two embryos with the intention to provide the resulting individuals with a resistance to the human immunodeficiency virus (HIV) disease (The Guardian, November 26, 2018), is, regrettably, a good illustration of such instrumentalization. Given the current state of knowledge on the actual function of CCR5 genes and potential off-target effects from the technique (Greely Citation2019), scientist He and his team seem to have disregarded the interests of the resultant children (and the prospective parents) in favor of their own interests. In their hope for a breakthrough in the field of HGE, and thus fame and profit (Greely Citation2019, 142), they disregarded the primacy of interests and welfare of resulting individuals born via the premature procedure. It is therefore arguable that they fail to demonstrate respect for human dignity in such instance. “Human dignity” if interpreted in this way – that is, as a means of avoiding instrumentalization of the resultant individuals – seems to have a more substantive place in the current context of HGE. Still, the case for a right to a genuine genetic identity has not been made even on the ground of “human dignity.”

2.3. Protection of “species identity”

If a right to a genuine genetic identity is not plausible following the grounds underpinning the current international provisions, the question then is whether there is a kind of “genetic identity” that international law intends to protect. Looking at the preparatory and drafting process of the 1997 Declaration, it is arguable that the “identity” in mind is of human identity, or species identity. This is because the need to protect and safeguard the integrity of “human species” was widely adopted in the earlier drafts of the 1997 Declaration (see Division of the Ethics of Science and Technology Citation1999, 118, 122, 126, 131) (notwithstanding that the phrase was substituted with “human family” in the final version).Footnote6 The intention to protect the human species is also acknowledged in the preparatory work on the Oviedo Convention: the Working Party noted that the term “identity” of the human being covers both “membership of the human species (so ruling out hybrids) and the individual’s genetic identity” (Steering Committee on Bioethics Citation2000, 10). Although both collective and individual interests are emphasized in the Convention, it seems that what is protected under Article 13 is a collective interest of not having tampered genomes prior to birth. The intention behind the protection of this “genetic identity” arguably stems from the fear that modification will cause unforeseeable mutations to the genome or bring about a change in human nature itself (Marks Citation2002, 115; CoE Citation1997, para 89). Preserving humanity, in this context, may be interpreted as preserving the identity and integrity of human beings against certain biotechnological advances (Andorno Citation2011, 57).

The above discussion suggests that it is unlikely that a legitimate claim for a right to a genuine genetic identity can be established. It is neither scientifically plausible, nor can adequate justification be found in the current international instruments. Hence, we argue that a right to retain a genetic identity does not provide an adequate basis to govern the ethical acceptability of HGE. Although there is a general global consensus in favor of a ban on the clinical use of HGE, with an emphasis on protecting the identity and integrity of human beings, it seems to us that none of the international documents offer useful guidance on this issue. The advances of science demand a precise meaning and consideration of the impact of prohibiting HGE (Montgomery Citation2018); or at least a closer consideration of what it means to preserve humanity. We suggest, in line with Montgomery’s (Citation2018) recommendation to re-examine the current ban under Article 13 of the Oviedo Convention, that the international framework may be more nuanced and better regulate HGE if it directly engages with the question of what it means to be a human, and whether humans have a genetic identity that needs to be protected as a part of human heritage. These questions should therefore be included in the ongoing ethical and regulatory debate on HGE.

3. A right-to-know “genetic identity”

In this section, we examine another conceptualization of “genetic identity.” This understanding answers the questions of how responsible translational pathways of HGE can be (in the view of protecting the interests of resulting children) should the technique be introduced to the reproductive setting. Particularly, we explore a right-to-know one’s genetic background where, in this context, one’s “genetic identity” entails knowledge about one’s genetic parents (or the individuals who contributed to their conception) and the mode of conception (see, e.g. Frith Citation2001, 480). A right-to-know is often linked with one’s narrative identity interest and it is this interest that we would like to highlight in the regulations of HGE. In this section, we first set out the conceptual grounds for a right-to-know. We then argue for a right-to-know for the prospective children born via HGE based on a narrative account of identity. We explain how narrative identity should be conceptualized in the context of HGE and why it deserves ethical and legal attention as part of governance of HGE.

3.1. The conceptual basis for a right-to-know for prospective children born via HGE

In order to plausibly establish the claim for a right-to-know in the context of HGE, we must first clarify what information is at stake and the need for disclosure of such information. Unlike adoption and third party assisted reproduction, there seems to be no concern about a third party’s identity in the case of HGE (at least in the usual circumstance without involving gamete/mitochondrial DNA donation from a third party) (Primc Citation2018, 106). Thus, what is more relevant and pertinent for the resulting children in the case of HGE is to discover the fact that the child has been genetically modified prior to conception (Ravitsky Citation2017, 5 in which the author notes that there is a lack of discussion on whether the genetically edited individuals would have a right to know that their genomes were edited before birth).

Drawing from the theories on a right-to-know in the context of adoption, paternity proceeding and third party assisted reproduction (except for the case of MRT, which will be dealt with in more detail shortly), at least three (overlapping) grounds are applicable for a right-to-know for the prospective children born via HGE. First, children’s right to information has gained legal and judicial recognition as part of human rights. In particular, such a right is recognized as an aspect of privacy rights through Article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights (see, e.g. Gaskin’s case [1989]; Mikulic’s case [2002]; Odievre’s case [2003]). Secondly and relatedly, the international as well as UK law have widely recognized the significance of personal development, including the formation of self-identity (see, e.g. Rose’s case [2002]). As such, establishing personal identity is seen as part of one’s private life with the formative function of identity also emphasized. Thirdly, the ascertainment of truth is generally seen as a good practice in serving the interest of children (see, e.g. Re T [2001]; Re F [1993]).

Drawing from the above grounds, we argue for a right-to-know for the prospective children born via HGE on the ground of narrative identity interest (more below). This differs from the approach adopted in the UK MRT debate. It is worth elaborating on this matter to draw lessons for the HGE debate. The UK policy making process in the mitochondria debate is led by the argument that mitochondrial genes are qualitatively and quantitatively insignificant in developing the resulting child’s personal and physical traits (Appleby Citation2018). In its consultation process, the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (“HFEA”) (Citation2013, para 6.69) highlighted in its advice to the UK Government that the general permissibility of the technique is, inter alia, based on the (presumed) insignificant amount (that is about only 0.1%) and role of mitochondrial DNAFootnote7 in an individual’s overall genetic constitution. Following the advice from the HFEA, the UK government concluded that mitochondrial DNA does not affect the personal traits of children (DoH Citation2014a, Citation2014b). This eventually led to the final decision to allow MRT in the clinical setting.Footnote8 This narrow “scientific” conceptualization of the genetic identity in the UK regulatory debates also led to other consequences which affect the rights of the individuals who donate and who are born as a result of MRT: the former have a right to anonymity and the latter thus have no right to identifying information about the donor.Footnote9

The consequences arising from such conceptualization of “genetic identity” has led to considerable academic debate (De Campos and Milo Citation2018; Appleby Citation2018; Turkmendag Citation2018; Douglas Citation2018; Brandt Citation2016). The primary criticism is that there seems to be an inclination towards genetic essentialism in the UK government’s reasoning, in the sense that a seemingly small contribution of mitochondrial DNA does not affect “who you are.” Turkmendag (Citation2018, 74) describes this as a “calculus of genes” – a form of reasoning based on “a percentage of calculation of DNA.” Turkmendag (Citation2018, 57) warns that this genetic-nature basis should not be given “privileged standpoint” as to the effect of how human rights are accordingly granted. This resonates with Wolf’s (Citation1995, 350) notion of geneticism, albeit in a slightly different context,Footnote10 in which she cautions against the harm of geneticism where it signifies the use of genetic conceptions to construct and support power relationships – some dominate and others are deemed inferior. This seems to have happened in the mitochondria debate. Mitochondria donor-conceived children are arguably subordinated to those born as a result of gamete-donation because mitochondrial DNA donated by a third party is deemed to have an insignificant effect on the resulting person’s overall identity and thus the right-to-know (genetic parents) as established in gamete donation is not extended to mitochondrial donor-conceived children (Turkmendag Citation2018).

Although, as we pointed out earlier, it is not the third party information that is the concern for HGE, the lesson that we would like to draw from the MRT policy debate is that an individualistic genetic-based account of identity – one which has dominated the MRT debate – should not be adopted in the context of HGE. Rather, we argue for a right-to-know one’s genetic identity based on narrative identity interests. We now elaborate on how we conceptualize narrative identity in the context of HGE by laying out the main characteristics of narrative identity. We then discuss the role of the information (that is, the fact of being born genetically modified) on one’s narrative identity and further explain its ethico-legal implications on the resultant children born via HGE.

3.2. Conceptualizing narrative identity

A narrative conception of “identity” has been widely applied in social science (see, e.g. Somers Citation1994; McAdams Citation2011). While this article cannot provide a comprehensive account of “narrative identity,”Footnote11 it draws attention to several main characteristics commonly referred to as a narrative account of identity. Narrative identity can be formed via storytelling – we construct our stories to make sense of our life (Scully Citation2017, 39; NCB Citation2012, para 4.7). Although this story is constructed internally, it is relational in the sense that we construct our story according to not only our own view, but also others’ perception of us (Scully Citation2017). It is also relational in that external factors affect how we construct our stories as well. Hence, narrative identity is formed through multiple factors, including our life experience, genetic makeup and biological characteristics (Postan Citation2017, 81–82). As these factors are constantly changing, so are our narrative identities.

Since self-narrative is relational, it is closely related to social identity which usually goes beyond individual and family and is constructed by social and/or cultural factors. The social identity of a child born genetically modified may be associated with the social image of such act as perceived by the society, which could include the policy makers (Haimes and Timms Citation1985, 77, albeit in the context of adoption). For instance, how the media reports the use of HGE will likely have a plausible impact on the self-conception of the resultant child (Scully Citation2017, in the context of MRT). In line with this thinking, if the fact of being genetically modified is purposefully kept hidden by parents and the social institution (for instance, the law or the government), it may also influence how one perceives oneself (if the child ever finds out).

In short, we conceptualize narrative identity as follows: it is in the form of self-conception (storytelling) and it is dynamic. Narrative identity is not over-individualistic considering its relational construction in that it may be influenced by the third party view and external factors. Noting this, the claim made here is thus not vulnerable to the criticism that rendering genetic knowledge as vital to one’s identity reinforces the notion of genetic essentialism or determinism (De Melo-Martín Citation2014, 33) because our position does not suggest that such information of the past (i.e. in regard to the mode of conception) is sufficient and determinative for shaping a coherent narrative. We agree with Ravitsky’s (Citation2014) view that defending a right-to-know certain information does not imbue any necessity to that piece of information. However, only if the information can make a significant difference in one’s life, is defending such a right meaningful (Ravitsky Citation2014). In the context of HGE, it is important to focus on the impact of this information (the truth of being born genetically modified) rather than the type of information (that it is genetic information).

3.3. The roles of information on narrative identity and the ethical weight of narrative identity

There are two prominent (closely related) functions of knowing the fact of being genetically modified on children’s narrative identity in the context of HGE. First, it promotes coherence – knowing one has been genetically modified before birth is pivotal for the resultant child in contributing (again, not determining) his/her self-conception and to make sense of his/her own identity. This is due to the “interpretive and structural role” that genetic information can play in making sense of one’s identity as a whole (Postan Citation2017, 41). The knowledge of our circumstance of birth is considered as our past or personal history. This information of the past helps to connect the dots and justify why we take certain actions (Somers Citation1994, 616). Apart from health and safety concerns to individuals and the population, such a piece of information is so important for the individual child to make sense of him/herself, especially if the body experiences any unusual conditions due to the complexity of HGE (see, e.g. Gyngell, Douglas, and Savulescu Citation2017, 504–506).

Secondly, it ensures authenticity – if one’s self-narrative were formed due to false information, one may develop a distorted identity (Blustein Citation1999, 23). Authenticity can be loosely defined as being true to ourselves (Varga and Guignon Citation2020). Being “true” to ourselves can be seen in two aspects. First, it relates to self-determination, which may be understood as being the author of our life as we define ourselves and are in control of our stories (Marshall Citation2009, 99). Second, it relates more closely to self-realization in line with the idea that “there is a true or real you already inside yourself waiting to be discovered or uncovered” (Marshall Citation2009, 99). Knowing the real “us” thus directs us “to realise” what we already are (Marshall Citation2009, 99). It is the latter that this article is concerned with in the context of HGE. Inaccurate beliefs about the past may undermine the individual making sense of their physical and social environment, therefore compromising his/her capacity to create a trustworthy autobiography (Bortolotti and Sullivan-Bissett Citation2018, 263; Postan Citation2017, 83). Lillehammer (Citation2014, 106) observes that although everyone may be aware that some facts about our genetic origins are unknown to us (e.g. our distant biological relatives; some of our ancestors), there is another scenario that is ethically problematic: having information based on the “false belief that one’s knowledge of these origins is accurate or complete.” It is “wrong” because it involves a “false consciousness” that keeps the individuals from their genuine interests “in the service of the interests of others” (Lillehammer Citation2014, 107).

Additionally, the right-to-know the truth is an essential condition of being autonomous. This is indicated by Spranzi and Brunet (Citation2014) who argue that everyone should have the freedom to choose bits and pieces and decide which is relevant for them in making sense of who they are. Phillips (Citation2007, 105) also argues that people who do not have a strong sense of identity are not able to “think reflectively, make choices and plan their lives.” Hence, a right-to-know is important for children in acquiring accurate information and such knowledge offers real opportunities for one to make informed choice (Lamport Citation1988), thus promoting one’s autonomy (Scully Citation2017, 42). In the context of HGE, a right-to-know will allow the resulting children to discover their medical history, monitor their health, and allow them to make an informed decision about their future reproductive choices (since the modifications that they were subjected to may be passed to their descendants). Given that one reason for the use of HGE is to prevent the transmission of a genetic disease, resultant individuals also deserve to know the medical history that led their parents to use HGE. This, in turn, also affects how they construct their narrative identity.

Therefore, we stress that this conceptualization of “genetic identity” deserves greater attention from policy makers in the context of HGE. This is because such a right, if successfully established, may be a way to safeguard the interests of children born as a result of the procedure due to the impact this could have on the children’s sense of identity. This is further strengthened by health and safety considerations, particularly because of the as yet unknown implications of the procedure; and by policy reasons, in that transparency would increase the accountability of clinicians and policy makers to the society at large (e.g. better or more information would allow societies to hold relevant institutions accountable for their policies [see Kaufmann and Bellver Citation2005, 4]).

4. Conclusion: summary and further research

This article analyzed two conceptualizations of “genetic identity” relevant to the HGE debate. First, drawing on the current international provisions, we argued that a right to retain genetic identity cannot be soundly established due to both conceptual and practical ambiguities. Hence, such a right does not constitute a valid basis to determine the legality and ethicality of HGE. We highlighted that “genetic identity” in this context is interpreted as to protect human (species) identity or the humanity. We therefore suggest further conversation on questions related to “preserving humanity” in the context of HGE.

Second, we argued that the concept of “genetic identity” is best understood as part of “narrative identity.” If HGE is legally allowed for reproductive purposes, a right-to-know one’s genetic identity (that is the circumstance of birth) should be given more weight in the regulatory debate of HGE with the focus on narrative identity interests. This is important because it may lead resulting individuals to make better informed decisions (e.g. future reproductive decisions, given the heritable effects from HGE). In addition, a right-to-know is also important for the resulting children for health and safety reason since they will be the first human trials, and for a transparent policy which creates greater accountability of the policy makers and clinicians. However, we have yet to discuss the details of how to implement and enforce a right-to-know in the context of HGE and its wider implications on other mode of assisted reproduction. There is currently no definite structure which legally enforces a right to be told the method of conception (as compared to a right-to-know the identifying or non-identifying information about the third-party donors in reproduction) (Douglas Citation2001). This raises another research area worthy of further examination.

While this article has explored the relationship between genetics and identity via a legal and regulatory framework, it must be noted that the governance of HGE, in practice, has changed in response to the development of science and technology. For instance, as Martin et al. (Citation2020, 237) observe, the increased capacity to manipulate the human genome prior to birth is already “putting pressure on the de facto international moratorium on human germline engineering.” Hence, it remains to be seen how the concept of “genetic identity” would eventually be adapted in the existing framework to shape the development of HGE.

Supplemental material

Supplemental Material

Download MS Word (12.2 KB)

Acknowledgement

The authors thank three anonymous reviewers for their constructive feedback on our manuscript. Many thanks too to the editors of this themed issue.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).

Notes

1 Scientist He Jiankui is charged of “illegal medical practice” and has been sentenced to three-year imprisonment and a fine (Nature News, January 3, Citation2020).

2 Note, whether the clinical application of HGE can be categorized as “therapeutic” remains contentious. For instance, Mills (Citation2020, 129) observes that the claim for “therapeutic” use in the context of HGE is misleading because the technique does not treat an existing individual but rather bring an individual with certain preferred characteristics into existence.

3 MRT involves replacement of unhealthy mitochondria with a healthy one from a third party. In the UK, it is used to prevent the transmission of serious mitochondrial diseases. Note, it has been argued that “mitochondria replacement technique” is a misleading language when the procedure is in fact a “nuclear genome transfer” (see, e.g., Nisker Citation2015).

4 “Germline,” as Juengst explains, ends in an organism’s reproductive cells since germline technically means the lineage of dividing cells within an organism that link its embryonic stage with its fully differentiated reproductive cells.

5 According to Juth (Citation2016, 418), genetic determinism connotes the view that “a person is a product solely of his genes” and other factors such as the environment become less significant. A closely related concept is genetic essentialism that is the view that genes “determine the essence of who we are.” These concepts, although phrased differently, carry a common feature: that genes can explain human traits. What is problematic with the essentialism and determinism view is that it connotes excessive reliance on the impact of genes on the formation of human characteristics, thus giving genes “more causal power than what scientific consensus suggests” (Gericke et al. Citation2017, 1224–1225).

6 Article 1 of the Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights 1997.

7 It is worth noting that although mitochondria are commonly known as energy provider to the cells (thus providing the UK government with the justification that mitochondria play only a minor role in identity), this is open to dispute. For instance, Mcbride, Neuspiel, and Wasiak (Citation2006) suggest that there are extended roles carried out by mitochondria which include directing and controlling of cell cycle which eventually affects body capacity.

8 See, The Human Fertilisation and Embryology (Mitochondrial Donation) Regulations 2015.

9 Ibid, Regulation 11(c); section 31ZA(2A) where it provides that only non-identifying information of the mitochondria donors is allowed upon request.

10 The context that Wolf discusses is genetic discrimination due to the advance of genetic tests. The concern is that people will be given labels and thus disadvantaged based on genetic information. Instead of genetic discrimination, Wolf argues that the harm at issue should be deemed as “geneticism.”

11 For a brief overview of different theories of narrative identity, see for instance, Cho (Citation2018); Blasi and Glodis (Citation1995).

References

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.