124
Views
3
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Main Articles

Hegel and the Consequentia Mirabilis

Pages 357-364 | Received 05 Jun 2017, Accepted 14 Feb 2018, Published online: 13 Mar 2018
 

Abstract

In this paper I argue that Hegel’s treatment of dialectical inferences, in particular of Plato’s dialectics in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy, belongs to the history of the logical rule that, from Gerolamo Cardano to Bertrand Russell, is known as consequentia mirabilis (CM). In 1906 Russell formalises it as follows: and its correspondent positive form as My paper has two parts. First, I show that dialectical inferences, for Hegel, involve sentences of the form and . Hegel, following Plato, stresses that these inferences are das Wunderbare, the marvellous element of dialectical reasoning. In this sense Hegel’s view belongs to the history of CM from a perspective that is both terminological and logical. Second, I stress the peculiarity of Hegel’s CM. In a classical setting, the conditional is admissible and from we can, by CM, derive , and from , by CM, infer . However, in Hegel’s analysis it is evident that we can neither infer from , nor from . Rather, in dialectical inferences what we can validly infer from and is only .

Notes

1 On the relation between dialectical and classical logic see Gadamer Citation1976, Düsing Citation1976, Fulda Citation1978, 33–69, Kulenkampff Citation1970, Sarlemijn Citation1971, Butler Citation1975, 414–31, Günther Citation1978, Marconi (ed.) Citation1979, Priest Citation1989, 388–415. For a complete and critical appraisal of these and other canonical positions see Marconi Citation1979 (ed.), 20ff. For an analysis of the link between dialectical, transcendental and ‘common’ (or formal) logic see Nuzzo Citation1997, 39–82 and Nuzzo Citation2014, 257–73. The question about the logical meaning of dialectical inferences has gained a new attention in the last 20 years, also thanks to the attempts at reading Hegel in analytical perspective (see among others Horstmann Citation1984, Stekeler-Weithofer Citation1992, McDowell Citation1994, Brandom Citation2002, Ruggiu and Testa (ed.) Citation2003, Redding Citation2007, Nuzzo Citation2010). See Berto Citation2005 and Berto Citation2007, 19–39 for a detailed account of the meaning of dialectical inferences based on Brandom’s inferentialistic holism. See also Ficara Citation2013, Ficara Citation2014, Bordignon Citation2015.

2 Hintikka Citation1981, 109–10, 110.

3 The history of the interpretations of Plato’s Parmenides is immense. For a detailed philosophical discussion of the reception of Plato’s Parmenides from Plotinus through Hegel to Natorp see Gadamer Citation1991, 313–27.

4 Hegel 1969ff., Vol. 19, 80–81 English translation Hegel 1892ff., Vol. 2, 57–58.

5 These aspects are differently stressed in the interpretations of Hegel’s dialectics. Löwith Citation1971, 222 distinguishes the ‘positive abstraction from every determination that is immediately given in order to find the pure thought determinations’ and ‘the negative abstraction from those determinations that pertain essentially to a determination’. Following Hegel’s terminology, he calls the first concrete and the second abstract abstraction, stressing that dialectical thought avoids the latter and pursues the former. That dialectical inferences involve semantic ascent is a characteristic insight of non-classical readings of Hegel’s dialectic. For Marconi Citation1979, 9–84, 19ff. dialectic requires the application of terms to themselves. In dialectic, the usual restrictions of type do not work. The violation of the restrictions of type on the basis of classical logic (in which the classical rules hold) generates the emergence of antinomies. Findlay Citation1981, 132–39, 132 observes that dialectical inferences imply what he calls a metabasis, that is:

that genuine passage beyond premises that is also involved in passing from an object language to a meta-language […] and in which [a conclusion is implied] by its premises rather in the sense in which G. E. Moore said that to assert that it is raining is to imply that one believes that it is raining.

Kulenkampff Citation1970 claims that dialectic implies the attempt at expressing the semantic properties of the language within the language (in Tarksian terms, this means that the language contains its own truth-value).

6 Hegel 1969ff., Vol. 19, 82, English translation Hegel 1892ff., Vol. 2, 59–60.

7 Hegel 1969ff., Vol. 19, 82, English translation Hegel 1892ff., Vol. 2, 59–60.

8 The passages on Plato’s dialectics in Hegel’s Lectures on the History of Philosophy confirm, in my view, the reading of Hegel’s notion of negation in standard propositional terms I have proposed in Ficara Citation2014, 29–38. The question about possible formal counterparts of Hegel’s notion of negation is still a controversial one in the literature. Puntel Citation1996, 131–65 claims that Hegel’s conception of negation is ‘not intelligible’. Among the classical works on Hegel’s concept of negation see Henrich Citation1978, as well as Düsing Citation2012, Chapter 1, Cortella Citation1995, Landucci Citation1978, Koch Citation1999, 1–29, Perelda Citation2003, Redding Citation2007, Chapter 3, Viellard-Baron Citation2013, 46–68, Pippin Citation2014, 87–110. Among the works on the link between Hegel’s negation and the non-classical logical tradition the essays collected in Marconi (ed.) Citation1979 are worth mentioning. Berto Citation2005, 284ff. examines the relationship between holistic inferentialism and Hegel’s dialectics, focusing in particular on the meaning of dialectical negation as material incompatibility. In Ficara Citation2014, 29–38 I highlight the continuity, but also the difference, between Hegel’s determinate negation and glutty negation. Wolff Citation1986, 107–28 highlights that the background of Hegel’s notion of negativity is the Kantian distinction between logical and real opposition. On Hegel’s and Kant’s notion of negation see also more extensively Wolff Citation1981.

9 For the history of consequentia mirabilis see Bellissima and Pagli Citation1996. An analysis of the philosophical meaning of CM-arguments can be found in D’Agostini Citation2002, D’Agostini Citation2009, Chapter 10.

10 Bellissima and Pagli Citation1996, 7.

11 See Bellissima and Pagli Citation1996, 11–12.

12 Theaetetus 170, XXII, 219–20 (translation from Hamilton and Cairns Citation1961).

13 Aristotle Metaphysics Gamma IV, 8 1012 b 12–22 (translation from Barnes Citation1984).

14 Questiones disputatae de veritate, Qu. I, Art. 5 (2) (translation from Mulligan Citation1952). See also Bellissima and Pagli Citation1996, 202. Centrone Citation2012, 127–57, shows that Bolzano’s arguments against Lambert’s critique of CM are also an important step in the history of CM.

15 Russell Citation1906, 159–202.

16 On the differences (as well as the debate about the differences) between CM and reductio arguments see Bellissima and Pagli Citation1996, 153.

17 As Kneale Citation1957, 62–66, 62 writes: ‘Like Aristotle, the Stoics used argumentation of this kind as a weapon against skepticism, for example, to confute those who said there was no proof, and it may be that through St Augustine’s Si fallor sum they inspired Descartes’ Cogito ergo sum’. See also Bellissima and Pagli Citation1996, 127.

18 The question about the irrefutability of both truth and philosophy is at the core of Hegel’s analysis and critique of ancient scepticism. See Hegel 1969ff., Vol. 2, 229ff.; Hegel 1969ff., Vol. 3, 159ff.; Hegel 1969ff., Vol. 19, 358ff.

19 Hegel 1969ff., Vol. 19, 82 English translation Hegel 1892ff., Vol. 2, 59–60.

20 I take this as formal expression of ‘the set of all sets which are not members of themselves is member of the set of all sets which are not members of themselves’.

21 See Priest and Routley Citation1984, 92–93. I agree with Priest and Routley Citation1984 about the formal closeness between dialectical and paradoxical inferences: both are sound arguments conveying a true contradiction. However, I stress that Hegel has a different view of the conclusion of a paradoxical inference than the one endorsed by Priest and Routley in Citation1984.

22 See for example Sainsbury Citation2009, Chapter 6.2. The connection is explicitly addressed and explained by D’Agostini Citation2002 and D’Agostini Citation2009, Chapters 10 and 11. It is also hinted at by Bellissima and Pagli Citation1996, 151ff.

23 A possible way to express the Liar paradox (L) formally is:

(L)

L: L is false (this is the formal expression of the Liar sentence ‘this sentence is false’)

The Liar sentence immediately implies:

L T’L’ (where ‘T’ is the truth predicate, and falsity is the negation of truth)

If we assume the truth-schema:

Taa

And apply it to L, we have

T’L’T’L’. The reconstruction is taken from Cook Citation2009, 171. The passage from L: L is false [formally expressed as: (L) ‘FL’] to LL is usually explained via the capture- and release-behaviour of the truth predicate in the T-schema (and the definition of falsity).

24 D’Agostini Citation2009, 140–41.

25 D’Agostini Citation2009, 113–14.

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.