282
Views
23
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Original Articles

Conceptions of truth in intuitionism

Pages 131-145 | Received 27 May 2003, Published online: 20 Feb 2007
 

Abstract

Intuitionism's disagreement with classical logic is standardly based on its specific understanding of truth. But different intuitionists have actually explicated the notion of truth in fundamentally different ways. These are considered systematically and separately, and evaluated critically. It is argued that each account faces difficult problems. They all either have implausible consequences or are viciously circular.

Notes

Often what the intuitionists attack under the name of LEM is not actually LEM but the principle of bivalence; strictly speaking, these two should be distinguished (see e.g. Dummett Citation 1978 , p. xix). However, under certain default assumptions, accepted by intuitionists, these two are equivalent (see e.g. Pagin Citation 1998 ). Consequently, in what follows I shall not be overly pedantic on this issue.

This is not the only possibility; some, most notably Heyting, rebut the whole notion of truth, and proceed directly to give a meaning-explanation of the logical constants, an explanation under which LEM etc. fail. But the basic question of this paper (see below), whether one should adopt the actualist or the possibilist approach, remains. I shall argue that Heyting is still deeply committed to the actualist picture, with all its problems; see below.

Also some recent constructivists such as Bishop and Bridges avoid talk of truth, but their explanation of constructivism closely leans on the possibilist picture (see below). Thus Bishop explains ‘the basic constructivist goal’ as being ‘that mathematics concern itself with the precise description of finitely performable abstract operations … Thus by “constructive” I shall mean a mathematics that describes or predicts the results of certain finitely performable, albeit hypothetical, computations within the set of integers’ (Bishop 1970, p. 53 my emphasis). Bridges, in turn, writes: ‘Constructive mathematics is distinguished from its traditional counterpart, classical mathematics, by the strict interpretation of the phrase “there exists” as “we can construct” ’ (Bridges Citation 1997 , my emphasis).

Some (e.g. Heyting; see below) rather want to eliminate the concept of truth and replace it e.g. by the possession of proof or by the possibility of proof. For my purposes here, however, this makes little difference.

Possibly just because of the problem just mentioned, namely, that Brouwer realized that very few would accept his austere actualist notion of truth and falsity as being actually proved and being actually refuted, respectively (van Stigt Citation 1990 , p. 248).

One might think that he was destined to fail, because it is arguable that the idea of an absolutely unsolvable problem makes no sense intuitionistically; see e.g. Heyting Citation 1958b , Dummett ( Citation 1977 , p. 17), Pagin Citation 1998 ; see also below.

I have put this together from three different, very similar sources: Brouwer Citation 1951 , Citation 1951 –52 and Citation 1955 .

I shall return to views like this (which I shall call ‘liberalized actualism’) later in the paper.

See van Stigt (1990, p. 212); cf. also the quote from Heyting Citation 1959 above. Brouwer appeals especially often to the meaninglessness of classical mathematics in Brouwer Citation1912.

See, however, the comments in Heyting Citation 1930 , quoted above.

Dummett Citation 1963 (not to be confused with Dummett Citation 1982 with the same title); in his 1978 introduction to the collection in which it was published Dummett regarded this paper ‘as very crude and as mistaken in many respects’ (Dummett Citation 1978 ).

Very recently, Dummett has become less cautious; he now states that ‘[t]he canons of correct reasoning in intuitionistic mathematics debar us from restricting true statements to those we have actually proved’ (Dummett Citation 2003 , p. 19).

See Prawitz ( Citation 1987 , p. 137). Prawitz originally presented it in a somewhat different form in a different context; I have slightly modified it.

In his early classic, 1959 paper ‘Truth’, Dummett had already recommended accepting the redundancy theory of truth.

See below. Note how similar Dummett's view here is to that of Heyting's.

Indeed, Dummett himself has often expressed the desirability of a non-temporal notion of truth.

To make the examples more concrete: take H to be e.g. the Paris-Harrington sentence (finitary Ramsey's theorem), and assume that the methods of proof available in Bob's time are limited to (a conservative extension of) Heyting Arithmetic HA, which does not prove H. It is, however, provable with the help of (intuitionistically acceptable) transfinite induction, which we may imagine to become accepted only much later.

The situation is even worse; the Gödelian argument goes through if one merely assumes that these methods are, even if not captured by a formalized system (i.e. not recursively enumerable, or Equation), at least somewhere in the arithmetical hierarchy (i.e. Equation for some n); cf. Appendix.

Cf. note 5.

This is because ‘A is not provable’ is true (according to intuitionism) if and only if it is provable; a proof that A is not provable entails that AB holds for any B, and thus in particular that A → ⊥, that is, that ¬A, cf. Dummett ( Citation 1977 , p. 17).

Not as a reaction to Prawitz but already before their debate begun.

The set of natural numbers is effectively generated, and the standard model of arithmetic is recursive (it is the only recursive model of PA), whereas the totality of proofs (if the idea is assumed to make sense) cannot be even arithmetical; see Appendix. Hence the former notion is much more simple and accessible than the latter. Therefore, it would be quite preposterous to be realist only with respect to the latter but not with respect to the former.

Quoted in Brouwer Citation 1912 !

Although, as I have argued, it is a widespread mistake to count Dummett as an adherent of this view.

While later surveying the literature, I have found out that the same question (‘What kind of possibility?’) has been raised, and sometimes a related argument hinted, by others: Parsons Citation 1983 (passim), Citation 1986 , Citation 1997 , George Citation 1993 , and Moore Citation 1998 . For me, however, the argument occurred independently of these; it was rather inspired by Sellars' criticism of phenomenalism (see Sellars Citation 1963 ). Interestingly, also Parsons ( Citation 1986 ) notes the affinity between intuitionism and phenomenalism.

Cf. e.g. Brouwer Citation 1933 , Heyting Citation 1956b , Troelstra ( Citation 1969 , pp. 3–4), Dummett ( Citation 1977 , p. 19), Prawitz Citation 1987 , Citation 1994 , Martin-Löf Citation 1995 .

Timothy Williamson once suggested in conversation that there is one more option, namely metaphysical possibility. I am personally inclined to agree, but the resulting view would certainly be quite alien for the anti-metaphysical spirit of intuitionism, and I doubt that no intuitionist is prepared to base intuitionism on this notion.

See e.g. Sundholm Citation 1983 and the many references therein.

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.