1,195
Views
6
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Testing the NHS: the tensions between personalized and collective medicine produced by personal genomics in the UK

ORCID Icon
Pages 227-249 | Received 05 Sep 2016, Accepted 13 Jun 2017, Published online: 24 Jul 2017

Abstract

This study examines direct-to-consumer genetic testing (DTCGT) in the UK using the Social Construction of Technology framework to draw conclusions about how commercial genotyping is being shaped by principal groups involved with the technology. Different tests are available including single nucleotide polymorphism genotyping for ancestry and health information, the latter being the focus of this study. I conducted interviews with DTCGT users, and genetics clinicians who had either been consulted about DTCGT or who were willing to discuss their views. This paper is about one of the study’s three themes, the NHS. DTCGT seemed to provide a point of focus for conflict between personalized and collective medicine in the UK, rather than being its cause. This suggests that DTCGT is more likely to achieve stability by virtue of being superseded by new technologies, rather than by achieving closure.

Introduction

Direct-to-consumer genetic testing (DTCGT) has been available for purchase on the Internet for 10 years. The DTCGT market offers numerous types of test; the focus for this project is the testing that claims to provide information about individual risk for common complex diseases. These tests are often sold as part of a genome-wide scan of hundreds of thousands of single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs), also known as SNP genotyping, that provide information on a range of traits including ancestry, physical traits, genetic disease, carrier status and pharmacogenomics as well as common complex disease risk (Leachman et al. Citation2011).

Facilitated by convergent developments in biotechnology, information technology and the Internet (Wright et al. Citation2011), DTCGT capitalizes on neoliberal policies that emphasize individual consumerism. The effect of these policies on health care has been to devolve responsibility for health to individuals resulting in a group of autonomous consumers of health-care services. Individuals are being encouraged to exercise accountability by managing their health and the risks to it, which DTCGT marketing capitalizes on (Tutton and Prainsack Citation2011). Knowledge that was previously the preserve of genetics clinicians, imparted in controlled clinical environments, has been democratized and made available to the public without recourse to the medical establishment (Borry, Cornel, and Howard Citation2010). Companies’ marketing tactics employ tropes of personalization to emphasize the advantages of information for making lifestyle and health choices in an autonomous, confidential manner (Arribas-Ayllon, Sarangi, and Clarke Citation2011). However, despite companies’ astute marketing, there are powerful counterclaims about the accuracy of the science on which genotyping is based (Janssens et al. Citation2008). There are also concerns about the public’s ability to understand the risk information they are sold without genetic counseling (Collins, Wright, and Marteau Citation2011). In addition, health professionals’ accountability to patients is challenged by their misgivings about the utility and potential harm that the information from commercial SNP genotyping could cause (Kraft and Hunter Citation2009). DTCGT is particularly problematic in this regard because of the capacity of genetic knowledge to cause harm to the individual and also to their relatives. So whilst the privacy and opportunity to exercise autonomy associated with DTCGT are presented as positive attributes by some (Juengst, Flatt, and Settersten Citation2012), the potential consequences of any breach of confidentiality could be severe (Finlay et al. Citation2016). These potentially divergent views about DTCGT represent the kind of challenge to society’s moral order that formed the basis of the calls for regulation of commercial genomics and its lack of stabilization as a technology (Evans and Green Citation2009). Thus DTCGT can be seen as a contested technology, which this study sought to examine in the UK context.

Background

Early research into DTCGT mostly comprised analyses of website material or surveys as to who might engage with DTCGT or how they might interpret results, rather than directly investigating the impact of DTCGT per se. Website analyses by Lachance et al. (Citation2010) and Singleton et al. (Citation2012) found a predictable bias toward positioning the benefits of testing, rather than a balanced presentation of advantages and disadvantages or limitations of testing. Content was variable within and across different sites, which could appear confusing and difficult to understand for some. Saukko et al. (Citation2010) undertook a qualitative analysis of nutrigenomic testing websites. Nutrigenomics companies sell supplements on the basis of genotyping a more limited range of SNPs thought to relate to metabolism rather than common complex disease risk, but this study’s findings appear applicable to the wider commercial genomics market. The study is noteworthy because the authors suggested that the boundary work performed by regulators and researchers to separate medical testing from commercial genomics is circumvented by companies who legitimize their products by positioning them as lifestyle products. Whilst companies selling SNP genotyping for common complex disease risk, ancestry and physical characteristics are not using testing to sell other products, their tropes of empowerment to enable positive lifestyle choices seem similarly designed. This is highlighted in an analysis of the discourse on websites for the three main personal genomics companies in 2007–2010, deCODEme, Navigenics and 23andMe. Whilst there were differences between all three websites, consumer empowerment was a common trope, suggesting that personalized health information could facilitate healthier lifestyle choices and thus reduce disease risk. The authors suggest that marketing rhetoric promising greater self-knowledge to alleviate future risk manages to obscure the uncertainty associated with SNP genotyping data (Arribas-Ayllon, Sarangi, and Clarke Citation2011).

Early survey research investigated what motivated people to consider testing, how they might interpret test results and whether information about the risks and limitations of testing would influence their decisions. Women with a history or family history of breast or ovarian cancer were found to choose testing less frequently when the risks of testing were included in mock websites. These findings suggest that the positive framing of DTCGT websites, as illustrated by the website analysis studies cited above, may attract the unwary with a concern about their health history (Gray et al. Citation2009). McGuire et al. (Citation2009) surveyed Facebook users in the United States of America (USA) (though not through Facebook) about DTCGT. Almost half of the cohort was aware of DTCGT, although fewer than 10% had tested. However, two-thirds of the respondents suggested that they would consider testing and a third indicated that they equated testing with diagnostic information. Whilst an indication does not equate to action, these results prompted the authors to conclude that health-care services needed to prepare to be consulted by DTCGT users seeking advice about test results. Adding to concerns about this increased demand on health services, a UK-based survey of people on the TwinsUK register established that, while a much smaller proportion of survey respondents in the UK claimed to be aware of DTCGT, enough would consider testing (depending on the price) to prompt similar warnings about the impact on health-care providers (Cherkas et al. Citation2010). A survey by Leighton, Valverde, and Bernhardt (Citation2012), which compared Facebook users’ interpretation of mock test results with those of genetics counselors in the USA, found that whilst the Facebook users found the results easy to understand, they interpreted their meaning differently from the genetics counselors. The authors suggested that people require support to understand the nature of testing information.

The first published empirical work involving users of DTCGT was McGowan, Fishman, and Lambrix’s (Citation2010) study in the USA. They found that these early adopters were curious about their genomes, knowledgeable about genetics and did not appear to suffer harm as a result of their test results or make any significant changes to their lifestyle. These findings were confirmed by later studies of genotyping test users including a mixed methods study of early adopters in Switzerland (Vayena et al. Citation2012). More recently the longitudinal PGen study conducted by George Church’s group in Boston surveyed users of DTCGT (Carere et al. Citation2016). They found that this cohort’s understanding of genetics was also relatively high before and after testing but their confidence in applying their genetics knowledge was reduced after testing, possibly as a result of their experience of receiving results. However, in line with studies outlined above, users did not report any increased anxiety after testing.

However, despite the considerable literature about DTCGT published by scientific genetics, medical, ethics, law and sociology communities, at the time of commencement of this study the experience of DTCGT in the UK represented a metaphorical “black box” (Lynch et al. Citation2010; Bijker, Hughes, and Pinch Citation2012). Accordingly I chose to investigate DTCGT in the UK context using Pinch and Bijker’s Social Construction of Technology (SCOT) model. The choice of framework is deliberate, as my intention is to shed light on the arguments and contested nature of DTCGT, specifically examining relevant social actors’ experiences within the wider context of the UK’s National Health Service, as I shall explain.

Using SCOT to examine DTCGT in the UK health-care context

Rather than simply viewing SNP genotyping as a laboratory test, the competing claims and discourses it provokes indicate that DTCGT warrants analysis as an assemblage that is being socially constructed and shaped by the discourses and actions of the actors involved with it. In this context discourses are understood as practices of sharing and developing beliefs and understanding through discussion, evaluation and interpretation in order to produce knowledge about the technology (Lessa Citation2005). In SCOT, these principles are applied to

  • relevant social groups of actors, in this case test users resident in the UK and NHS genetics clinicians

  • the wider social context, in this case the NHS

  • actors’ interpretative flexibility

  • the stabilization and closure of disputes surrounding the technology (Bijker, Hughes, and Pinch Citation2012).

In their critical review of SCOT, Klein and Kleinman argue that assuming relevant social groups are homogeneous misses the potential influence that individuals may have on technology owing to their political, economic or professional influence (Klein and Kleinman Citation2002). They advocate for more detailed analysis of the constituent members of relevant social groups whilst also paying attention to the wider context for a more comprehensive analysis. Accordingly I shall describe the characteristics of participants in the users’ and genetics clinicians’ groups in the Methods section.

The use of SCOT illustrates the influence of human intervention on SNP genotyping in the UK, which is crucial to challenge deterministic views. A technologically deterministic position could absolve people from responsibility in their engagement with the technology (Wyatt Citation2008), while a bioethical one could assume a paternalistic interpretation, which risks interpreting findings in a non-symmetrical manner. Given the potential impact of genetic information on people and their social groups, an exploration of the social construction of this technology seems to provide a germane approach to understanding the impact of DTCGT in the UK.

Thus the wider social context of the UK and, more specifically, the NHS is central. From its inception in 1948 the NHS has provided care free at the point of access to UK citizens on the basis of a collective medical model. The medical profession has influenced NHS patients’ access to health interventions relying on patients to trust that this is decided in their best interests. This has increasingly translated into rationing and policy shifts associated with economizing and the public taking responsibility for their health to discourage dependency on the NHS (Department of Health Citation2010; Klein Citation2013). Health-care professionals’ gatekeeping role and formerly sacrosanct expertise is arguably challenged by people’s direct access to health information, altering trust-based professional–patient relationship (Tutton Citation2014). The original collective medical model is shifting from what Klein calls the paternalistic “church,” where care is dispensed to a trusting public, to the consumerist “garage” to which people drop in and take what they want (Klein Citation2013, 306). Thus, the NHS’ iconic status in British culture, representing democracy and the welfare state (Busby and Martin Citation2006), is increasingly challenged by demands from medical innovation, societal expectation for personalization and reduced funding owing to political incentives for austerity (Bambra Citation2013).

Genomics exemplifies the individual, particularly in relation to human genomics, which has provided DTCGT companies with the basis for focusing their marketing on personalization and individual responsibility. This aligns with the simultaneous globalization of neoliberal ideas including emphasis on individual choice and consumerism, tropes that DTCGT companies foreground (Arribas-Ayllon, Sarangi, and Clarke Citation2011). This polarization of collective and individual is considered by Donna Dickenson. She suggests the DTCGT companies’ tropes of personalization in the name of empowerment and individual responsibility for health undermine collective medicine in an increasingly commercial domain (Dickenson Citation2013). The contradiction inherent in DTCGT companies’ marketing personalized health information on the basis of population-derived genomic data is central to her argument that commercial genomics is simply profiteering. This is despite the collapse or takeover of many DTCGT companies which suggests failure in that regard otherwise (Vorhaus Citation2012).

These interdependent but conflicting aspects of collective and individualized medicine are emblematic of this study. Thus, the study focuses on users and genetics clinicians as the two relevant social groups influencing DTCGT within the social context of the NHS. Interpretative flexibility is key for illuminating the influence of different views of technology presented to different audiences, at different times with different intentions and outcomes (Bijker, Hughes, and Pinch Citation2012). Whilst Williams and Edge (Citation1996) argue that the infinite possibilities that could be proposed are unhelpful in analyzing how closure is achieved, analysis of variations in accounting can be particularly valuable when claims are repeatedly disputed (Potter and Mulkay Citation1985). The concept is thus important for this study, as inconsistent and contradictory views are evident in the data.

In order to understand the impact of DTCGT in the UK I collected and analyzed the stories, experiences and thoughts of two relevant social groups involved with the technology in the UK. The findings discussed in this paper focus on the tension between personalized and collective medicine that DTCGT creates, one of the three themes evident in the study’s data.

Methods

DTCGT was relatively novel and un-researched in the UK context at the time this study commenced. The SCOT framework was chosen to illuminate how the relevant social groups of test users and genetic clinicians engage with DTCGT in different and competing ways for social, economic, professional and regulatory reasons. It was obvious to involve test users resident in the UK as one of the relevant social groups, owing to their direct experiential knowledge of DTCGT and the potential for them to seek help from NHS genetics services. Literature related to DTCGT suggested that genetics clinicians would have influential views and shared understandings about DTCGT owing to their clinical specialism. These were likely to contrast with the views of users or producers of the technology so these practitioners were involved as the other relevant social group for the study. In addition, with their status as experts in clinical genetics, they would be most likely to be called upon to interpret results and provide counseling in the event of any concern. Both groups have interests in DTCGT technology and each shares experience and knowledge of DTCGT, which Bijker refers to as a “technological frame” (Bijker Citation2010, 69). But their conflicting interpretations and knowledge claims provide a suitable starting point for examining the influence of their interests on the technology (Bartley Citation1990).

The other group of health-care professionals that could be relevant in the UK context is General Practitioners (GPs); their role as gatekeepers for specialist consultations in the UK (Louden Citation2008) indicates that they are likely to be users’ first port of call for help with interpretation of health test information. However, as the literature indicates lack of understanding of genomics by most doctors, genetics clinicians presented a more relevant group, given their experience of advising and supporting people in relation to genetic conditions (Edleman and Eng Citation2009; Salari Citation2009).

With approvals from Research Ethics and Research and Development committees in place, I sought participants for the study. To be eligible to participate, users had to be an adult UK resident and have purchased DTCGT that included health information. This purposeful sampling was intended to facilitate discussion about their engagement with the technology and their views on the relationship of the health-related aspects to their health care in the NHS context. I purposely used the Internet to recruit users. At the time of the study personal genotyping was largely marketed and sold online; I hoped that test users would be conversant with finding information about genomics online and would come across invitations to be involved in research. However, unlike genetics clinicians whose geographical locations could be easily established, DTCGT users were people who Brown and Webster describe as being without embodiment (Brown and Webster Citation2004). This is due to their identities as DTCGT users being linked to their online personas rather than their physical, embodied ones. I thus anticipated having to use several approaches to recruit participants to this group.

Recruitment of users was surprisingly easy however. A webpage describing the study (now removed) and a blog post on “genomesunzipped,” a website providing independent, expert commentary on commercial genomics requested volunteers (http://www.genomesunzipped.org/ n.d.). These Internet sites were quickly located by most of the user participants. Members of the UK branch of the International Society of Genetic Genealogists (ISOGG) discovered the study website within hours of it going live. Some volunteered for the study or informed others about it. Other participants were either biosciences researchers who read the blog post on genomesunzipped or people known to participants, as snowball sampling was also used for recruitment (Atkinson and Flint Citation2001). Consequently, most of the group of user participants had similar characteristics to the early adopters described in McGowan et al.’s study of DTCGT users in the USA (McGowan, Fishman, and Lambrix Citation2010). The early adopter profile of this relevant social group suggests that they are likely to be more informed about the technology and to enthuse others. This was evident from the over representation of participants who were working in genetic research and curious about DTCGT, or who were avid genetic genealogists. All the users had tested with 23andMe, having purchased a test from the company prior to changes made as a result of FDA intervention in 2013 (Conley Citation2013). Some had also tested with other companies for genetic genealogy information (see for details). Seventeen interviews were conducted over four months in 2012, 2 on the telephone and 15 face-to-face at the participants’ choice of location.

Table 1. User participants’ demographic and DTCGT information.

Despite their known geographical locations, clinicians were more difficult to access. A number of strategies were used, including emails to British Society of Genetic Medicine Members (BSGM), leafleting delegates at a BSGM conference and contacting regional Genetics Services in the UK to raise awareness of the study. Recruitment initially targeted clinicians who had counseled patients about DTCGT, but was very slow. Subsequently it emerged that this was likely to be due to few referrals for DTCGT, despite concerns that clinical genetics services could be overwhelmed by requests for consultations with the worried well who struggled to interpret their genotyping report (Hogarth, Javitt, and Melzer Citation2008). So the inclusion criteria were broadened to include clinicians who were willing to discuss their views about DTCGT, whether they had encountered patients who had sought counseling or not. This resulted in 16 interviews with genetics clinicians of various professions over 11 months between 2012 and 2013 at the participants’ choice of location. One was on the telephone, 15 were face-to-face (see for a summary of Genetics Clinicians’ Information).

Table 2. Genetics clinicians’ professional information and consultations for DTCGT.

Interviews were semi-structured and in-depth, mixing specific and open questions as indicated by the participant’s experiences. Questions and prompts covered demographic information, types of testing used or encountered, referrals to discuss testing, people’s experiences of testing or counseling testers as well as general exploration of their views about DTCGT. Interviews were audio recorded and I transcribed them to familiarize myself with data from the interviews onwards. Interviews commenced after participants had consented to participation including the use of verbatim, de-identified excerpts. To maintain confidentiality, data extracts in this paper are attributed to user participants using synonyms and occupation, but to clinicians using an assigned code that identifies their place in the sequence of clinician participant (CP) interviews and their profession. These different approaches also maintain a distinction between the two groups in the data analysis.

The transcript data were analyzed with the principles of impartiality and symmetry in mind. This was deliberate in order to avoid attributing my own views to the participants and to enable me to adopt an objective and symmetrical approach to the data from the two relevant social groups studied here in relation to DTCGT specifically. An iterative approach was taken to the data analysis to elicit the themes within the texts of the interview conversations (Creswell Citation2013). Repeated reading of the text, making notes about patterns and disparities, and using reflective notes about the interviews informed my thinking with the data. The data were coded inductively with in vivo codes that emerged from the participants’ discourse (Ryan and Bernard Citation2000). The data were then re-read alongside the literature and deductively collected into categories. The final stage of analysis commenced by writing and connecting the categories and literature in a more direct manner. From this perspective, I used further reading and writing to interact with the data and explore its categories alongside my thoughts (Coffey and Atkinson Citation1996). From this iterative process, three overarching themes became evident across the participants’ data. These were

  1. Socializing DNA: the influence of social networks on the participants’ technological frame and discourse about DTCGT

  2. Personalizing DNA: participants’ individual ideas about DNA in the context of SNP genotyping and their incorporation into participants’ genetic identities or clinical practice

  3. Testing the NHS: the problem of expectations for personalized medicine in the context of collective medicine provision

The third theme of personalized medicine and its challenge for the NHS is the focus of this paper.

Findings – testing the NHS

Public support for the NHS has been unstinting since its inception (Klein Citation2013). Whilst not surprising, the organization that the public champions is arguably more simplistic than the complex one in which so many have vested interests and for which there are different visions of its obligations and how to meet them. The two groups in this study volunteered opposing beliefs about personal genomics in the NHS context, illustrating the contested nature of commercial genotyping in this context. There was predictable support for personalized medicine (though not necessarily at NHS expense) from some DTCGT users, while clinicians described support for collective medicine and the need to protect the NHS’ scarce resources. Tensions between these two groups focused on responsibility, either for individual health or service provision, and the concepts of empowerment of the public versus professional expertise. Areas of agreement focused on pharmacogenomics and a shared support for the NHS, though these are unlikely to indicate imminent stabilization of the technology. I shall discuss each of these sub-themes in turn, using excerpts from the data to illustrate the points made.

Responsibility

Discussion from some test users about personal information and responsibility for health suggests uptake of policy moves toward individuals taking more responsibility for their own health (Department of Health Citation2010). However, they also indicate adoption of companies’ tropes of personalization and empowerment, which Van Lente suggests is due to technologies becoming fixed in specific language that directs beliefs and behavior (Van Lente Citation2000).

Users who referred to the health information from testing in relation to responsibility drew attention to the opportunity for making lifestyle alterations or seeking health screening based on the health information provided by DTCGT. One user had sought medical advice, as her test results suggested an increased risk of cancer (supporting her family history). Similarly, Ian, who does not have a background in genetics or biotechnology, stresses the need for cancer screening.

I must get my PSA count done, at my age I should be doing it anyway. I haven’t got any symptoms but I should and having got the information [from DTCGT] it’s really highlighted it to me that I should. I’m very aware of that but I haven’t done anything about it yet … . Ian (retired)

This illustrates personal responsibility for health monitoring, not least perhaps because there is no effective screening program for prostate cancer. However, the value of PSA testing is unclear bringing Ian’s assertion into question (Public Health England Citation2016). Ian stresses his personal responsibility repeatedly. However, his lack of action is in common with other users none of whom described making lasting lifestyle changes or having interventions for disease-risk management in light of test results. This supports findings in the study of early DTCGT adopters in the USA and the REVEAL study (McGowan, Fishman, and Lambrix Citation2010; Chilibeck, Lock, and Sehdev Citation2011). It also refutes concerns about the impact on the NHS of concerned citizens seeking interventions following DTCGT that Dickenson forecasted (Dickenson Citation2013).

Clinicians’ concerns in respect of responsibility were focused on providing genetic counseling and protecting the NHS from the repeatedly cited potential drain on scarce resources by privately initiated testing (Nuffield Council of Bioethics Citation2010; Dickenson Citation2013). The clinicians who had counseled people following DTCGT voiced concerns.

One of the things I find difficult is that we get, when these things come up the people are very, very upset and they want to be dealt with on an urgent basis, and so that’s really expensive time, that kind of emergency time. And I find it really hard to justify taking up emergency time but I don’t want to see the patient suffering either. CP2 (Doctor)

This represents a unique reference to counseling someone in distress following DTCGT in this study. Patients’ distress is emphasized, as is their expectation for counseling, to highlight the moral challenge of juggling finite resources. This is framed in a manner that suggests this occurs more often than evidence suggests, possibly in a similar adoption of prevailing discourse about anticipated pressure on Genetics Services from DTCGT as users’ adoption of tropes of personalization and empowerment. Concerns about use of scarce resources being taken up by counseling people who had initiated testing privately were more widely expressed despite little evidence of it. Most inferred that DTCGT was outside the remit of clinical genetics. This nurse defends the NHS responsibility for rationing, pointing to an impasse in balancing personalized and collective medicine.

If people … want to get their 23andMe, I‘m not bothered. I am bothered if they then use up healthcare resources to interpret findings that are meaningless for a test that wouldn’t be offered on the healthcare system. And you know I don’t know how we deal with that. I mean I don’t think this just applies to genetic tests. It applies to body scanning, it applies to lots of things. CP5 (Nurse)

An experienced doctor, with academic responsibilities in addition to a clinical role, expressed a more equivocal view. Arguments for both collective and personalized medicine are presented, possibly due to a strategic view of genomic technologies’ potential diagnostically and for NHS revenue generation through developing commercial biotechnology opportunities.

It comes down to whether you want to take a public health approach or an individual healthcare view of it and we all oscillate between those positions. There’s clearly a danger that unregulated, genetic testing causes a lot of people a lot of distress, exposes unrecognised non-paternities, makes people anxious who are already anxious which is why they did the test, doesn’t resolve their anxiety, it just makes them go to the doctor and pester him who then has an opportunistic cost because he’s so busy seeing that person that he doesn’t see the next one, and you can portray a very negative perspective. On the other hand you can also say that if you empower the individuals to care for themselves and make those tests available in a controlled way, quality control them well, we could massively expand genetic testing and people’s appreciation and understanding of it because it’ll touch more and more of their lives and you’ll just make it more and more part of routine healthcare which is where it’s now capable of moving. So I kind of sit in the optimistic let’s have a go camp. CP10 (Doctor)

The explicit references to both sides of the responsibility debate and the interpretative flexibility demonstrated in recognizing that they are not mutually exclusive suggests a vision that supports genomic technologies generally rather than dismissing DTCGT. This locates DTCGT within the wider context of genomic technologies including Genome England’s 100,000 Genomes Project and increasing use of genome sequencing in mainstream medicine, which are being forecast to shift genetics clinicians roles toward more educational and advisory responsibilities (www.genomicsengland.co.uk n.d., AGNC Citation2014, 1; Clayton-Smith et al. Citation2015).

The suggestion that genomic information could be empowering depends on understanding genomics and its role in contributing to people’s health information. This could be interpreted as having expertise in genomics; the issue of how user and clinician participants equate this to clinical genetics expertise is explored next.

Empowerment or expertise

Those of the study’s group of users with a primary interest in health results and genealogy expressed support for personalized health information commensurate with what Bunnik et al refer to as the personal utility of DTCGT (Bunnik, Janssens, and Schermer Citation2015). Given NHS policies highlighting the importance of patient engagement and empowerment, people’s pursuit of health information from personal genomics is perhaps unsurprising. However, this has fueled criticisms of health-care professionals dismissive of patients’ efforts, owing to their paternalistic approach and ignorance of contemporary genotyping technologies (Jordens, Kerridge, and Samuel Citation2009; Bunnik, Janssens, and Schermer Citation2015). Several users in this study were among them, voicing strong opinions about their perceptions of deficits in NHS staff knowledge and service provision. Their technological frame of DTCGT is that it provides important personal health information. It is worth remembering that at least half the group of users in the study has occupational experience of genetics, whilst those who are genealogists have experiential expertise in genotyping, having purchased more than one test. Whilst the group of clinicians all has the credentialed clinical genetics expertise that Collins and Evans describe, their experiential expertise of SNP genotyping was arguably not comparable to the users’ (Collins and Evans Citation2007). However, their technological frame of DTCGT is of technology based on contingent science, one referring to it as snake oil. Not all were disparaging, but their view of DTCGT as providing meaningless information sets clinicians in opposition to those users whose technological frame of DTCGT saw it as empowering.

Several users voiced skepticism about doctors’ understanding of DTCGT, describing dismissive attitudes. This supports assertions that the democratization of genomic information could erode trust between patients and health-care professionals (McGuire and Burke Citation2008; Tutton Citation2014). The following excerpt is from a user who works in bioinformatics and had tested partly due to her curiosity about genomics as well as personal and familial health issues that she wished to investigate. This seems to have been driven by her need for autonomy so that she could access and consider her health information independently.

The health service seems to work with doctors being in charge with the patient being a kind of vessel that they look at and treat and examine; I rather baulk at that. I find it really frustrating and difficult to deal with, so I like having control over it and I’d rather skip the doctors giving me a pile of information I already know and sometimes don’t agree with, and I like to have the information there and be able to mull it over in my own time. I do find doctors’ appointments are really pressured as well, you get 10 minutes to talk to a Consultant sometimes and you have to say everything in that 10 minutes, coherently; and you don’t get another appointment for months for instance and it’s just a horrible, horrible experience … I think the medical profession ought to get with it, make use of it [genomics]. I think they are pretty stuck in the past. I think it’s appalling the lack of uptake of new technologies in the NHS. It’s just a huge big sluggish monster and they are barely doing any sequencing of people as far as I can tell. I don’t think they are any good at preventative or diagnostic medicine, it’s all reactive what the NHS does and I wish they’d get more proactive and do things ahead of time rather than letting people get ill and then put a sticking plaster over the top of it. Laura (Biologist)

Despite her self-knowledge and understanding of biology, Laura’s emphatic statement suggests that medical hegemony leaves her disempowered. The promise of personalization and empowerment offered by DTCGT is attractive partly because it circumvents conventional medical power and gatekeeping, bolstering her sense of agency. However, her observation about medicine’s lack of integration of genomics to explain the NHS’ inability to help her appears to justify her use of DTCGT. Here, her flexible interpretation of genomics arguably equates DTCGT with sequencing and invests genomics with diagnostic potential that has yet to be realized (Tutton Citation2014).

In contrast, clinicians questioned the value of SNP genotyping and some view public understanding of genetics with a deficit model compared to their clinical expertise. One genetic counselor and a doctor implicitly position clinicians as having expertise.

People access tests for very different reasons and unfortunately I think the public do think it’s CSI. CP1 (Scientist)

This counselor’s experience of patients’ understanding of genomics is equated with a popular television crime drama. The suggestion is that fictional representations of genetics are absorbed and repositioned as truth by people consulting clinical genetics services. Here the contingent nature of the scientific basis for DTCGT could be equated to fictional representations of science, implying that clinical genetics expertise is needed to explain genetic information. Another clinician’s experiences also suggested that people view genetics deterministically.

I think that people often start off in a position where genetics is really something very important and very deterministic. Umm, if they don’t start from that position then I’m not so worried about it but I think it’s really common in UK society to think that genetics determines much more than, much more in a clear way than I think it does. CP4 (Doctor)

This view invests the majority of British society with deterministic understanding of genetics on the basis of this doctor’s experience, the implication being that DTCGT users could be misled and caused needless harm by DTCGT results. Indeed Harris et al.’s argument that deterministic interpretation of genetic information is supported when accessed through the Internet strengthens this concern (Harris, Kelly, and Wyatt Citation2016). However, neither of these extracts indicate consideration for people represented by some users in this study who do have genomics knowledge and who felt they were able to understand their test results, or the finding that none of the users, whatever their interpretation of DTCGT, reported experiencing significant or lasting concerns from testing.

While some of these users’ views suggest a utopian view of personalized medicine that they criticize doctors for shunning, the clinicians’ support for collective medicine necessitates a different view of the utility of personal genomics. Juxtaposing these views results in ongoing conflict between these relevant groups about the technological frame of DTCGT as well as having repercussions for the relationship of trust between patients and health-care professionals as predicted (McGuire and Burke Citation2008; Wyatt et al. Citation2013). Brown and Webster suggest that where trust fails, health-care practice is unfeasible and, whilst this point does not appear to have been reached by these participants, these excerpts do point to a shift in the clinician–patient relationship to a more distrusting position or at least a less readily assumed trust (Brown and Webster Citation2004). However, while SNP genotyping for common complex diseases has the potential to disrupt trust between patients and practitioners and fuel the ongoing disputes about personal genomic technology, there are aspects on which participants in both groups shared common opinions, which I shall complete the discussion with.

Common ground

The data in this study suggested that some of the participants in both groups shared similar views about two areas relating to DTCGT in the NHS context. Firstly, there were shared understandings about the value and significance of the NHS both as the country’s principal health-care provision and as an institution strongly associated with the UK’s national identity, endorsing Klein’s assertion that the NHS is a “national treasure” (Klein Citation2013, vi). Secondly, there were similar views among some participants in both groups about DTCGT’s pharmacogenomics information.

Support for the NHS was evident in some participants’ references to examples from their practice or experience as users of the NHS to illustrate a shared perception of people’s preferences for its services over seeking health-care information independently. Clinicians referred to people’s faith in the NHS based on their experiences as health-care professionals. Whilst this may seem to be contradictory to the earlier suggestion that DTCGT users’ trust in the NHS is being challenged by personalized medicine, not all users expressed these views; some users were more equable. One genetics researcher was eager to separate her self-professed “narcissistic curiosity” in pursuing DTCGT from the NHS’ responsibilities.

The NHS doesn’t have the resources to do these things for people who are just interested or curious … here people really generally trust the NHS and I think most British people have huge affection for the NHS and there’s a lot of respect for it … it’s something we are really proud of and so we tend to trust the NHS, even though it’s not perfect. Maria (Geneticist)

The commonly described recreational aspect of personal genomics is often a motivation for testing, driven by people’s curiosity (Prainsack et al. Citation2008). As with many other geneticists and genealogist users in this study, Maria viewed her test as satisfying her curiosity about her DNA rather than related to health care or substituting any NHS responsibility for her health. Her reference to the NHS’ lack of perfection suggests an acknowledgement that, despite its dissonance with the consumerism of personalized medicine, the collective medical model is acceptable and widely supported by the public because of its centrality to British national identity (Gershlick, Charlesworth, and Taylor Citation2015).

The second aspect of shared views about SNP genotyping was more surprising, being about pharmacogenomics, the information from SNPs that suggest variance in pharmacodynamics or kinetics (the physiological processes affected by drugs or those which metabolize them, respectively). This could be seen as fortunate, given the dependence of patients on qualified health-care professionals for prescribing of medicines. However, the contingent nature of the science underpinning disease-risk information from SNP genotyping is equally applicable to pharmacogenomics and arguably has more serious implications if prescribing decisions are made on the basis of its assumed utility.

Richard Tutton’s exploration of the historical context of personalized medicine refers to the rhetorical devices used to promote the compelling idea that pharmacogenomics will result in drug treatments designed for individuals rather than populations (Tutton Citation2012). The expectation that genomics will deliver individually designed drug regimens in a new molecular iteration of personalized medicine has not been realized. It has resulted in the concept being modified along more achievable lines, such as stratified medicine where people are assigned to groups of treatment according to genetic differences (Tutton Citation2014). In light of this it is significant that some participants in both the relevant social groups being studied spoke positively about the potential of pharmacogenomics to improve health care. The following extracts from one user of DTCGT and one clinician illustrate this point. The first is from a researcher in public health who envisages negotiating her future drug therapy with her GP.

On my genetic thing it says there’s a sensitivity to Metformin. I obviously get it from my mother [who reacted badly to it] and Metformin is such a typical drug for giving to type II diabetic patients so it’s going to be interesting if I ever get to the point of having a GP say he’s going to put me on Metformin, [I wonder] how much notice he’s going to take when I say “I don’t think so.” Carol (Public Health researcher)

Carol’s suggestion about her future treatment envisages a confrontational consultation and prescription without any discussion or consideration of concordance. Her refusal of it based on her pharmacogenetics SNP analysis illustrates her use of interpretative flexibility in relation to DTCGT. She had earlier dismissed results relating to disease risk because of the inconclusive nature of SNP genotyping but seems to be more deterministic about the pharmacogenetics information. Carol’s justification for this on the basis of her DTCGT results ignores her family history of intolerance of this drug. Family history is thought to be more reliable than SNP genotyping in health information and is probably contributing to her thinking in this regard, though here she chooses to focus on her DTCGT results.

Some clinicians also demonstrated interpretative flexibility in referring to pharmacogenomics positively, having dismissed its utility for common complex disease-risk information. One doctor gave a colorful vision of his ideas for anticoagulant prescribing on the basis of SNP genotyping.

I can see the value in these types of things; you know Warfarin, [prescribing] Warfarin’s a black art. When I worked on the wards I was told, “Start this guy on Warfarin. Prescribe him 10 [mg] today, 10 tomorrow and 5 the day after that and test his INR [blood clotting time].” And you’d test their INR and some guy’s INR hadn’t shifted from baseline so you’d whack them another 10 and some little old woman was ready to bleed out all over the ward because her blood was so thin, it was like dilute orangeade. So it was a guess, but now we’re getting a handle on that. A little bedside SNP so we’d know how to prescribe, and then start them on Warfarin. But that’s not predicting a genetic disease; we need this information to look at how to dose you. CP13 (Doctor)

Titrating this risky anticoagulant medication within the narrow margins of safe efficacy indicates the clinical challenge involved and its associated stress. Using interpretative flexibility, this doctor imagines a solution to that challenge. However, this potential clinical application for SNP genotyping in the NHS is not so far supported by research. Genotyping patients for Warfarin metabolism and prescribing dosage accordingly does not appear to make any significant difference to the efficacy or safety of this difficult and potentially dangerous treatment (Stergiopoulos and Brown Citation2014). This casts doubt on the efficacy of point-of-care SNP genotyping for Warfarin dosing, supporting concerns about clinicians’ lack of knowledge in this regard (UK Pharmacogenetics Study Group Citation2006).

Participants’ mutual support for pharmacogenomics could represent a point from which the relevant social groups involved in DTCGT in the UK could negotiate socially acceptable aspects of genomics technology in the NHS in future. This could provide an opportunity for stabilization of the technology, as Hedgecoe and Martin (Citation2003) argued in relation to pharmacogenomics. However, the likelihood of this is small and its foundations are tenuous in the extreme, given the contested basis of personalized medicine in the context of SNP genotyping in particular, as these findings show.

Conclusion

Findings from this study suggest that DTCGT is a less disruptive technology in the UK context than early concerns forecast. This is evidenced firstly by the study’s group of users’ lack of concern or uptake of interventions on the basis of test results. Secondly, the lack of impact on NHS clinical genetics services is demonstrated by difficulties recruiting genetics clinicians with experience of DTCGT to the study and participants’ reports of few enquiries about post-DTCGT counseling. However, this should not obscure the conflict between some of the participants in relation to the NHS context, which focused on the tension between personalized and collective medicine, responsibility and expertise.

The issue of who should take responsibility for individuals’ health is being exposed by DTCGT and, as Klein suggests, the NHS is currently in an ambiguous position in this regard (Klein Citation2013). The concepts of personalization and consumerism and the associated expectation of public responsibility are particularly challenging for the NHS in times of austerity. Arguably this is the predictable outcome of health policy that has increasingly emphasized health promotion, individual responsibility and choice, rhetorically at least (Klein Citation2013). Thus, it is not unreasonable of people to avail themselves of opportunities to obtain health information and to feel aggrieved when their efforts are dismissed by health-care professionals. Equally understandable are health-care professionals’ frustrations about the lack of transparency of commercial health information marketing and the significant restraints within which they are expected to provide services to an increasingly demanding public, some of whom appear to show little genuine engagement with responsibility for their health. This lack of engagement is despite adopting the language of commercial genomics companies in relation to DTCGT and using interpretative flexibility to assume belief in the promise of DTCGT technology to provide personalized health information.

Users’ experiential expertise is important in considering their level of engagement and understanding of what their genomic data are communicating. Most users in this study have knowledge of genetics from personal research or education, and have spent considerable time immersed in learning about personal genomics either independently or through their occupation. In addition their networking activities have facilitated the dissemination and development of what has been referred to as “technical know-how” (Evans and Plows Citation2007, 836). Users’ experiences of DTCGT could be referred to as lay-expertise, in a manner similar to studies by Kerr et al. about the public and their knowledge of genetics, Prior’s work on lay-expertise in medical sociology and Epstein’s work with HIV-AIDS activists (Epstein Citation1995; Kerr, Cunningham-Burley, and Amos Citation1998; Prior Citation2003). However, as these authors all indicate, ‘lay-expertise’ belies the complexity inherent in who lay actors are and what constitutes their expertise, as exemplified by the heterogeneous nature of this study’s group of users. In addition, investing users with expertise could be questioned in light of the interpretative flexibility demonstrated by some when extolling the virtues of their DTCGT information. Whilst their expertise in clinical genetics both unites the clinicians and informed their inclusion as a relevant social group for this study, their expertise in personal genomics is also questionable. Although credentialed, contributory experts in clinical genetics, most clinicians’ experience and expertise relate to chromosomal abnormalities and genetic mutations rather than SNP genotyping. Some are well versed in the literature relating to genomics and are able to cut through users’ apparent experiential expertise by critiquing the scientific basis of testing, the panels used for SNP analysis and the lack of inclusion of wider genetic anomalies related to specific conditions. However, they are mostly not engaged with the public who are buying DTCGT. Whether expert or not, understanding of personal genomics influences participants’ technological frames of DTCGT, setting many of them apart into those who support the personal utility of DTCGT and those who dismiss it as lacking utility and a threat to collective medicine.

Analyzing the views of users and genetic clinicians about DTCGT and the challenges for the NHS suggests that the potential for SNP genotyping technology to achieve stability in a health-care context in the UK is probably remote. While the relevant social groups in this study may suggest that DTCGT is a focus for the ongoing disputes around personalized versus collective medicine in the UK, I would argue that DTCGT per se is not the cause of that dispute. Rather it is the vehicle for participants’ expressions of concern as they are confronted with challenges to their respective perceptions of responsibility for health. Shared appreciation of the NHS was evident in both groups and some clinicians’ interpretative flexibility in relation to pharmacogenomics led to common visions with some users for its future potential. However, I would argue that these aspects of common ground are unlikely in themselves to lead to a resolution of the disputes about DTCGT in the near future, given the generally irreducible nature of the differences between these two groups’ views about responsibility and empowerment. It is more likely that the technology will be stabilized by virtue of being superseded by new problems such as whole genome sequencing and expectations of the information it will yield.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful for the invaluable support of my supervisors, Adam Hedgecoe and Michael Arribas-Ayllon at Cardiff University. I would also like to thank Michael Morrison and the anonymous reviewers for their comments and advice on earlier versions of this article.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.

Additional information

Funding

This research was conducted as part of a doctoral study funded by a +3 PhD studentship from the ESRC’s Wales Doctoral Training Centre.

References

  • AGNC. 2014. The Future Role of Genetic Counsellors in Genomic Healthcare. Association of Genetic Nurses and Counsellors. Accessed April 13, 2017. http://www.agnc.org.uk/media/925792/agnc_vision_statement_final.pdf.
  • Arribas-Ayllon, M., S. Sarangi, and A. Clarke. 2011. “Promissory Accounts of Personalisation in the Commercialisation of Genomic Knowledge.” Communication and Medicine 8 (1): 53–66. doi: 10.1558/cam.v8i1.53
  • Atkinson, R., and J. Flint. 2001. “Accessing Hidden and Hard-to-reach Populations: Snowball Research Strategies.” Social Research Update 33. Accessed April 4, 2016. http://sru.soc.surrey.ac.uk/SRU33.html.
  • Bambra, C. 2013. “All in it Together? Health Inequalities, Austerity and the ‘Great Recession’.” In Health in Austerity, edited by C. Wood. London: Demos. Accessed April 4, 2017. https://www.demos.co.uk/files/DEMOS_Health_in_Austerity_-_web.pdf?1379898927.
  • Bartley, M. 1990. “Do We Need a Strong Programme in Medical Sociology?” Sociology of Health and Illness 12 (4): 371–390. doi: 10.1111/1467-9566.ep11340397
  • Bijker, W. E. 2010. “How is Technology Made? That is the Question!” Cambridge Journal of Economics 34: 63–76. doi: 10.1093/cje/bep068
  • Bijker, W. E., T. P. Hughes, and T. Pinch. 2012. The Social Construction of Technological Systems: New Directions in the Sociology and History of Technology. Anniversary ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Borry, P., M. C. Cornel, and H. C. Howard. 2010. “Where are you Going, Where Have You Been: A Recent History of the Direct-to-consumer Genetic Testing Market.” Journal of Community Genetics 1 (3): 101–106. Accessed September 4, 2016. http://www.springerlink.com/content/1uk1w43425251412/. doi: 10.1007/s12687-010-0023-z
  • Brown, N., and A. Webster. 2004. New Medical Technologies and Society: Re-ordering Life. Cambridge: Polity Press.
  • Bunnik, E. M., J. W. Janssens, and M. H. N. Schermer. 2015. “Personal Utility in Genomic Testing: Is There Such a Thing?” Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (4): 322–326. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2013-101887
  • Busby, H., and P. Martin. 2006. “Biobanks, National Identity and Imagined Communities: The Case of UK Biobank.” Science as Culture 15 (3): 237–251. doi:10.1080/09505430600890693 doi: 10.1080/09505430600890693
  • Carere, D. A., P. Kraft, K. A. Kaphingst, J. S. Roberts, and R. C. Green. 2016. “Consumers Report Lower Confidence in Their Genetics Knowledge Following Direct-to-consumer Personal Genomic Testing.” Genetics in Medicine 18 (1): 65–72. doi: 10.1038/gim.2015.34
  • Cherkas, L., J. Harris, E. Levinson, T. Spector, and B. Prainsack. 2010. “A Survey of UK Public Interest in Internet-based Personal Genome Testing.” PLoS One 5 (10): e13473. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0013473
  • Chilibeck, G., M. Lock, and M. Sehdev. 2011. “Postgenomics, Uncertain Futures and the Familiarization of Susceptibility Genes.” Social Science and Medicine 72: 1768–1775. doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2010.01.053
  • Clayton-Smith, J., R. Newbury-Ecob, J. Cook, and L. Greenhalgh. 2015. The Evolving Role of the Clinical Geneticist. Clinical Genetics Society. Accessed April 13, 2017. http://www.bsgm.org.uk/media/956131/theevolvingroleoftheclinicalgeneticist_29.07.15.pdf.
  • Coffey, A., and P. Atkinson. 1996. Making Sense of Qualitative Data: Complementary Research Strategies. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
  • Collins, H., and R. Evans. 2007. Rethinking Expertise. London: University of Chicago Press.
  • Collins, R. E., A. J. Wright, and T. M. Marteau. 2011. “Impact of Communicating Personalized Risk Information on Perceived Control Over the Risk: A Systematic Review.” Genetics in Medicine 13 (4): 273–277. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e3181f710ca
  • Conley, J. 2013. If 23andMe falls in the forest, and there’s no-one there … Genomics Law Report Accessed September 4, 2016. http://www.genomicslawreport.com/index.php/2013/12/03/if-23andme-falls-in-the-forest-and-theres-no-one-there/#more-13198.
  • Creswell, J. W. 2013. Qualitative Inquiry and Research Design: Choosing among Five Approaches. Los Angeles: Sage.
  • Department of Health. 2010. Healthy Lives, Healthy People: Our Strategy for Public Health in England. Department of Health, The Stationery Office. Accessed March 15, 2017. https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/216096/dh_127424.pdf.
  • Dickenson, D. 2013. Me Medicine vs. We Medicine: Reclaiming Biotechnology for the Common Good. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
  • Edleman, E., and C. Eng. (2009). “A Practical Guide to Interpretation and Clinical Application of Personal Genomic Screening.” British Medical Journal 339: 1136–1140.
  • Epstein, S. 1995. “The Construction of Lay Expertise: AIDS Activism and the Forging of Credibility in the Reform of Clinical Trials.” Science, Technology and Human Values 20 (4): 408–437. doi: 10.1177/016224399502000402
  • Evans, J. P., and R. C. Green. 2009. “Direct-to-consumer Genetic Testing: Avoiding a Culture War.” Genetics in Medicine 11 (8): 568–569. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e3181afbaed
  • Evans, R., and A. Plows. 2007. “Listening Without Prejudice? Rediscovering the Value of the Disinterested Citizen.” Social Studies of Science 37 (6): 827–853. doi: 10.1177/0306312707076602
  • Finlay, T., S. Gibson, L. Koch, and S. Tocchetti. 2016. “Personal Genomics: Transparent to Whom?” In Genetic Transparency: Ethical and Social Implications of Next Generation Human Genomics and Genetic Medicine, edited by M. Dreyer, J. Erdmann, and C. Rehmann-Sutter, 113–146. Amsterdam: Brill Rodopi.
  • Genomesunzipped. n.d. Genomesunzipped: Public Personal Genomics. Accessed April 13, 2014. http://genomesunzipped.org/about.
  • Genomics England. n.d. The 100,000 Genomes Project. Accessed April 13, 2017. https://www.genomicsengland.co.uk/.
  • Gershlick, B., A. Charlesworth, E. Taylor. (2015). Public Attitudes to the NHS. London: The Health Foundation. Accessed March 30, 2017. http://www.health.org.uk/sites/health/files/PublicAttitudesToTheNHS.pdf.
  • Gray, S. W., C. O’Grady, L. Karp, D. Smith, J. Sanford Schwartz, R. C. Hornick, and K. Armstrong. 2009. “Risk Information Exposure and Direct-to- Consumer Genetic Testing for BRCA Mutations Among Women with a Personal or Family History of Breast or Ovarian Cancer.” Cancer Epidemiology, Biomarkers and Prevention 18 (3): 1303–1311. doi: 10.1158/1055-9965.EPI-08-0825
  • Harris, A., S. Kelly, and S. Wyatt. 2016. Cybergenetics: Health Genetics and New Media. Abingdon: Routledge.
  • Hedgecoe, A. M., and P. A. Martin. 2003. “The Drugs don’t Work: Expectations and the Shaping of Pharmacogenetics.” Social Studies of Science 33 (3): 327–364. doi: 10.1177/03063127030333002
  • Hogarth, S., G. Javitt, and D. Melzer. 2008. “The Current Landscape for Direct-to-consumer Genetic Testing: Legal, Ethical and Policy Issues.” Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 9: 161–182. doi: 10.1146/annurev.genom.9.081307.164319
  • Janssens, A. C. J. W., M. Gwinn, L. A. Bradley, B. A. Oostra, C. M. van Duijn, and M. J. Khoury. 2008. “A Critical Appraisal of the Scientific Basis of Commercial Genome Profiles Used to Assess Health Risks and Personalize Health Interventions.” American Journal of Human Genetics 82: 593–599. doi: 10.1016/j.ajhg.2007.12.020
  • Jordens, C. F. C., I. H. Kerridge, and G. N. Samuel. 2009. “Direct-to-consumer Personal Genome Testing: The Problem is not Ignorance – It Is Market Failure.” American Journal of Bioethics 9 (6–7): 13–15. doi: 10.1080/15265160902874411
  • Juengst, E. T., M. A. Flatt, and R. A. Settersten. 2012. “Personalized Genomic Medicine and the Rhetoric of Empowerment.” Hastings Centre Report 42 (5): 34–40. doi: 10.1002/hast.65
  • Kerr, A., S. Cunningham-Burley, and A. Amos. 1998. “The New Genetics and Health: Mobilizing Lay Expertise.” Public Understanding of Science 7: 41–60. doi:10.1177/096366259800700104.
  • Klein, R. (2013). The New Politics of the NHS: From Creation to Reinvention. 7th ed. Abingdon: Radcliffe Publishing.
  • Klein, H. K., and D. L. Kleinman. 2002. “The Social Construction of Technology: Structural Considerations.” Science, Technology and Human Values 27 (1): 28–52. doi: 10.1177/016224390202700102
  • Kraft, P., and D. J. Hunter. 2009. “Genetic Risk Prediction? Are We There Yet?” New England Journal of Medicine 360 (17): 1701–1703. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp0810107
  • Lachance, C. R., L. A. H. Erby, B. M. Ford, V. C. Allen, and K. A. Kaphingst. 2010. “Informational Content, Literacy Demands, and Usability of Websites Offering Health-related Genetic Tests Directly to Consumers.” Genetics in Medicine 12 (5): 304–312. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e3181dbd8b2
  • Leachman, S. A., D. G. MacArthur, M. Angrist, S. W. Gray, A. R. Bradbury, and D. B. Vorhaus. 2011. “Direct-to-consumer Genetic Testing: Personalized Medicine in Evolution.” In ASCO Education Book, 34–40. https://www.genomicslawreport.com/wp-content/uploads/2011/06/ASCO-DTC-Abstract.pdf.
  • Leighton, J. W., K. Valverde, and B. A. Bernhardt. 2012. “The General Public’s Understanding and Perception of Direct-to-consumer Genetic Test Results.” Public Health Genomics 15 (1): 11–21. doi: 10.1159/000327159
  • Lessa, I. 2005. “Discursive Struggles with Social Welfare: Restaging Teen Motherhood.” British Journal of Social Work 36 (2): 283–298. doi: 10.1093/bjsw/bch256
  • Louden, I. 2008. “The Principle of Referral: The Gatekeeping Role of the GP.” British Journal of General Practice 58 (547): 128–130. doi: 10.3399/bjgp08X277113
  • Lynch, M., S. A. Cole, R. McNally, and K. Jordan. 2010. Truth Machine: The Contentious History of DNA Fingerprinting. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • McGowan, M. L., J. R. Fishman, and M. A. Lambrix. 2010. “Personal Genomics and Individual Identities: Motivations and Moral Imperatives of Early Users.” New Genetics and Society 29 (3): 261–290. doi: 10.1080/14636778.2010.507485
  • McGuire, A. L., and W. Burke. 2008. “An Unwelcome Side-effect of Direct-to-consumer Personal Genetic Testing: Raiding the Medical Commons.” Journal of the American Medical Association 300 (22): 2669–2671. doi: 10.1001/jama.2008.803
  • McGuire, A. L., C. M. Diaz, T. Wang, and S. G. Hilsenbeck. 2009. “Social Networkers’ Attitudes to Direct-to-consumer Personal Genome Testing.” American Journal of Bioethics 9 (6–7): 3–10. doi: 10.1080/15265160902928209
  • Nuffield Council on Bioethics. 2010. Medical Profiling and Online Medicine: the Ethics of Personalised Healthcare in a Consumer Age. London: Nuffield Centre for Bioethics. Accessed April 4, 2017. http://www.nuffieldbioethics.org/personalised-healthcare-0.
  • Potter, R. J., and M. Mulkay. 1985. “Scientists’ Interview Talk: Interviews as a Technique for Revealing Participants’ Interpretative Practices.” In The Research Interview: Uses and Approaches, edited by M. Brenner, J. Brown, and D. Canter, 247–271. London: Academic Press.
  • Prainsack, B., J. Reardon, R. Hindmarsh, H. Gottweis, U. Naue, and J. E. Lunshof. 2008. “Personal Genomes: Misdirected Precaution.” Nature 456: 34–35. doi: 10.1038/456034a
  • Prior, L. 2003. “Belief, Knowledge and Expertise: The Emergence of the Lay Expert in Medical Sociology.” Sociology of Health and Illness 25 (3): 41–57. doi: 10.1111/1467-9566.00339
  • Public Health England. (2016). Prostate Cancer Risk Management: Programme Benefits and Risks of PSA Testing. Public Health England Gov.UK. Accessed April 15, 2017. https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/prostate-cancer-risk-management-programme-psa-test-benefits-and-risks/prostate-cancer-risk-management-programme-pcrmp-benefits-and-risks-of-psa-testing#references.
  • Ryan, G. W., and H. R. Bernard. (2000). “Data Management and Analysis Methods.” In Handbook of Qualitative Research, edited by N. K. Denzin and Y. S. Lincoln, 2nd ed, 769–802. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
  • Salari, K. (2009). “The Dawning Era of Personalised Medicine Exposes a Gap in Medical Education.” PLoS Medicine 6 (8): e1000138. Accessed April 4, 2017. http://www.plosmedicine.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pmed.1000138. doi: 10.1371/journal.pmed.1000138
  • Saukko, P. M., M. Reed, N. Britten, and S. Hogarth. 2010. “Negotiating the Boundary Between Medicine and Consumer Culture: Online Marketing of Nutrigenomic Tests.” Social Science and Medicine 70 (5): 744–753. doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2009.10.066
  • Singleton, A., L. H. Erby, K. V. Foisie, and K. A. Kaphingst. 2012. “Informed Choice in Direct-to-consumer Genetic Tests (DTCGT) Websites: A Content Analysis of Benefits, Risks and Limitations.” Journal of Genetic Counseling 21: 433–439. doi: 10.1007/s10897-011-9474-6
  • Stergiopoulos, K., and D. L. Brown. 2014. “Genotype-guided Versus Clinical Dosing of Warfarin and Its Analogues: Meta-analysis of Randomized Clinical Trials.” Journal of the American Medical Association Internal Medicine 174 (8): 1330–1338. doi:10.1001/jamainternmed.2014.2368.
  • Tutton, R. 2012. “Personalizing Medicine: Futures Present and Past.” Social Science and Medicine 75 (10): 1721–1728. doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2012.07.031
  • Tutton, R. 2014. Genomics and the Reimagining of Personalized Medicine. Farnham: Ashgate.
  • Tutton, R., and B. Prainsack. 2011. “Enterprising or Altruistic Selves? Making Up Research Subjects in Genetic Research.” Sociology of Health and Illness 33 (7): 1081–1095. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9566.2011.01348.x
  • UK Pharmacogenetics Study Group. (2006). Policy Issues in Pharmacogenetics: Policy Briefing. Accessed April 17, 2017. http://www.york.ac.uk/media/satsu/res-pgx/PGxpolicyissues2006.pdf.
  • Van Lente, H. 2000. “Forceful Futures: From Promise to Requirement.” In Contested Futures: A Sociology of Prospective Technoscience, edited by N. Brown, B. Rappert, and A. Webster, 43–64. Aldershot: Ashgate.
  • Vayena, E., E. Gourna, J. Streuli, E. Hafen, and B. Prainsack. 2012. “Experiences of Early Users of Direct-to-consumer Genomics in Switzerland: An Exploratory Study.” Public Health Genomics 15: 352–362. doi.org/10.1159/000343792 doi: 10.1159/000343792
  • Vorhaus, D. 2012. “Implications of Amgen/deCODE Deal for Genetic Testing Consumers.” Genomics Law Report. Accessed April 17, 2017 http://www.genomicslawreport.com/index.php/2012/12/10/implications-of-amgendecode-deal-for-genetic-testing-consumers/.
  • Williams, R., and D. Edge. 1996. “The Social Shaping of Technology.” Research Policy 25: 865–899. doi: 10.1016/0048-7333(96)00885-2
  • Wright, C., H. Burton, A. Hall, S. Moorthie, A. Pokorska-Bocci, G. Sagoo, S. Sanderson, R. Skinner. 2011. Next Steps in the Sequence: The Implications of Whole Genome Sequencing for Health in the UK. PHG Foundation Cambridge. Accessed September 4, 2016. http://www.phgfoundation.org/file/10363/.
  • Wyatt, S. (2008). “Technological Determinism is Dead; Long Live Technological Determinism.” In The Handbook of Science and Technology Studies, edited by I. Hackett, O. Amsterdamska, M. Lynch, and J. Wajcman, 3rd ed., 165–180. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Wyatt, S., A. Harris, S. Adams, and S. Kelly. 2013. “Illness Online: Self-reported Data and Questions of Trust in Medical and Social Research.” Theory, Culture and Society 30 (4): 131–150. doi: 10.1177/0263276413485900

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.