197
Views
4
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Original Articles

A Kantian-Brandomian View of Concepts and The Problem of a Regress of Norms

Pages 528-543 | Published online: 05 Jul 2019
 

ABSTRACT

According to the Kantian-Brandomian view of concepts, we can understand concepts in terms of norms or rules that bind those who apply them, and the application of a concept requires that the concept-user be sensitive to the norms governing its application. But this view faces some serious objections. In particular, according to Rosen, Glüer and Wikforss, this view leads to a vicious regress of norms. The purpose of this paper is to defend a version of the Kantian-Brandomian view of concepts against this objection. I argue that we can deal with this problem along the lines of a coherentist account of justification.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.

Notes

1. For a detailed defense of this interpretation regarding Kant’s view of concepts, see Ginsborg Citation1997, esp. 48–52. In addition, see Brandom Citation2010b, 297: ‘For Kant, intentional contents (whether what is endorsed is a judgeable content or a practical maxim) are articulated by concepts. And concepts are generically rules. That is to say that for Kant, concept is a normative concept. What they are rules for doing is synthesizing a unity of apperception’ (underline in original).

2. In line with this distinction of Kant’s, Brandom (Citation1994, 33) distinguishes between being subject to a norm and being sensitive to a norm.

3. On Kant’s view, the fundamental unit of cognition is a judgment, and we are rationally responsible for our judgments; moreover, concepts are nothing but predicates of possible judgments (see Kant Citation1998, A69/B94). Thus, for him, a concept is to be understood only in the context of a judgment (see Kant Citation1998, A68/B93). In this way, on his view, we are rationally responsible for our application of concepts. By contrast, the parrot is not rationally responsible for the sounds it makes.

4. See Wittgenstein (Citation1969, §§ 341–343). In addition, for a detailed discussion and defense of this point, see Lee Citation2014.

5. For a detailed discussion and defense of a Sellarsian coherence theory of justification, see Lee Citation2017.

6. As Hilary Putnam (Citation1975) points out, we engage in the social division of linguistic labor. For example, many of us including me cannot tell an elm tree from a beech true. Nonetheless, due to the social division of linguistic labor, I can correctly assert that elm trees are not beech trees, by deferring to some experts on the matter of the norms governing the application of the concept elm or the concept beech. In a similar vein, a person can defer to some members of her linguistic community on the matter of the norms governing the concepts she uses. Therefore, the application of a concept does not require that the concept-user herself be self-consciously aware of the norms governing its application. For the concept-user can engage in the social division of linguistic labor, so that her application of the concept can be guided by the relevant norms by the help of some other members of her linguistic community.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 384.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.