Publication Cover
Philosophical Explorations
An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action
Volume 23, 2020 - Issue 2
199
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Commentary

Reasoning to action

Pages 180-186 | Published online: 18 Jun 2020
 

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the authors.

Notes on contributor

Constantine Sandis is Fellow of the Royal Society of Arts and Professor of Philosophy at the University of Hertfordshire. He is the author of The Things We Do and Why We Do Them (2012), Character and Causation: Hume’s Philosophy of Action (2019), and Raisons et responsabilité – Essais de philosophie de l'action (2020).

Notes

1 Dancy (Citation2018), to which all page numbers in this commentary refer, unless otherwise specified.

2 Cf. Smith and Pettit (Citation1997, 73ff.)

3 Dancy also allows for considerations to favour having a particular emotion.

4 Prichard (Citation1932, 99).

5 In his Pécis for this Book Symposium Dancy writes: “Until we solve this problem my whole story about practical reasoning is unstable […] Until we do resolve the Prichard point, we have not yet managed even to understand the notion of a reason, since we do not know what it means to talk of a consideration favouring a type of response or favouring acting in a certain way. This is not a happy situation”.

6 I use the word “particularised” rather than “particular” because I suspect that what the latter denotes, at least as I use it, is not particular enough for what Dancy has in mind. After all, you can instruct me to act in a particular way that is very precisely defined, and any number of a fixed range of particular doings would still fulfil the instruction.

7 Not least because, for Dancy and Raz alike, “in believing we are as active as we ever are” (144).

8 See Ross (Citation1930, 6–7).

9 While Dancy recognises such a distinction in the case of belief, his defence of the primacy of the practical leaves no real role for things believed to play in the theoretical case.

10 But see Dancy (Citation2009) for a detailed defence of his deflationary approach to actions.

11 Dancy (Citation2009, 401). If we must apply the type/token distinction to actions at all, I see no reason why we can’t apply it to both doings and things done. The one is not a token of the other.

12 For details see Sandis (Citation2017).

13 In a footnote, Dancy quotes the following passage from Michael Stocker, without comment: “We fulfil duties by performing … act tokens … Nonetheless it is not a duty to perform any act token. For we could have fulfilled our duty by performing another act token of the appropriate type. For example, even though that returning of the book fulfilled the promise, many other returnings of the book would have done so as well” (Stocker Citation1968, 54; as quoted in Dancy Citation2018, 31, fn.3). Yet the “act tokens” that Stocker has in mind are not acts we perform but our particular performings of them. The acts we perform, such that of returning of the book, are what Stocker (in my opinion, wrongly) conceives of as act types.

14 We would do better, I think, to talk of believing-in-action and intending-in-action.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 233.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.