433
Views
5
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
ARTICLES

Spinoza, Boyle, Galileo: Was Spinoza a Strict Mechanical Philosopher?

Pages 45-64 | Published online: 02 Jan 2013
 

Notes

1What is known as the correspondence between Baruch Spinoza and Henry Oldenburg consists of 17 letters from Oldenburg to Spinoza and 11 from Spinoza to Oldenburg.

2R. Boyle, ‘Certain Physiological Essays’, in The Works of Robert Boyle, edited by M. Hunter and E.B. Davis (London: Pickering & Chatto, 1999–2000), vol. 2, 1–203.

3The term ‘physiological’ in Physiological Essays should be understood in the same sense as ‘physical’ or simply as that which concerns nature.

4J. Israel, ‘Spinoza as an Expounder, Critic, and “Reformer” of Descartes’, Intellectual History Review, 17:1 (2007), 59–78.

5C. Bontekoe, Brief Aan Johan Frederik Swetser, Gesegt Dr. Helvetius, Geschreven en uytgeeven tot een Korte Apologie voor den Grote Philosooph Renatus Descartes […], ('s Gravenhage, 1680).

6See P. Totaro, ‘ “Ho certi amici in Ollandia”: Stensen and Spinoza – science verso faith’, in Niccolὸ Stenone: Anatomista, geologo, vescovo, edited by K. Ascani, H. Kermit, and G. Skytte, (Rome: L'Erma di Bretschneider, 2000), 27–38.

7See E.D. Baumann, Franco¸ois dele Boe Sylvius (Leiden: Brill, 1949). For information about Sylvius and the University of Leiden around 1661 see also Dutch Culture in a European Perspective, vol. 1: 1650 – Hard-Won Unity, edited by W. Frijhoff and M. Spies (Assen: Royal van Gorcum /Palgrave Macmillan, 2004), 319.

8See letter 6 and letter 13.

9See W.N. Newman and L.M. Prinzipe, Alchemy Tried in the Fire (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2005), 212–13; W.N. Newman, Atoms and Alchemy (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2006), 210; J.T. Young, Faith, Alchemy and Natural Philosophy: Johann Moriaen, Reformed Intelligencer, and the Hartlib Circle (Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, 1998).

10See S. Nadler, Spinoza: A Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).

12See letter 11.

11All citations from Boyle's work are from: R. Boyle, The Works of Robert Boyle, edited by M. Hunter and E.B. Davis (London: Pickering & Chatto, 1999–2000). All citations from Spinoza's work are from Spinoza, Complete Works, edited by M.L. Morgan and translated by S. Shirley (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company Inc., 2002). All citations in Latin are from: Spinoza, Opera, im Auftrag der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften herausgegeben von Carl Gebhardt (Heidelberg: Carl Winters Universitätsbuchhandlung, 1972 [1925]).

13In letter 16, Oldenburg writes: ‘He [Boyle] asks you to consult the preface which he wrote to his Experiments on Nitre, so as to understand the true aim which he set himself in that work: namely, to show that the doctrines of the more firmly grounded philosophy now being revised are elucidated by clear experiments, and that these experiments can very well be explained without the forms, qualities and the futile elements of the Schools.’

14See H. More, The Immortality of the Soul, edited by A. Jacob (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1987), 4–21. The first version of this book was published in 1659, the second revised edition in 1662.

15See A. Gabbey, ‘What Was “Mechanical” about “The Mechanical Philosophy”?’ in The Reception of Galilean Science of Motion in Seventeenth Century Europe, edited by C.R. Palmerino and J.M.M.H. Thijssen, (Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers: 2004), 11–23.

16See A. Clericuzio, Elements, Principles and Corpuscles: A Study of Atomism and Chemistry in the Seventeenth Century (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2000), 143.

17See A Free Enquiry into the Vulgarly Received Notion of Nature (1686), edited by M. Hunter and E.B. Davis (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 61.

18This preface reached the printer at the last minute; it was inserted in the first edition between pages already numbered. As a consequence the preface with the definition dates from 1661 although the Essays were written earlier, probably in 1655 or 1656.

19Boyle, and most seventeenth-century chemists, used ‘principle’ and ‘element’ interchangeably.

20Cf. R.S. Westfall, The Construction of Modern Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 41.

22See ‘Letter from Wallis to Boyle (25 April 1666)’, in The Correspondence of Robert Boyle, edited by M. Hunter, A. Clericuzio and L. Prinzipe, 6 vols (London: Pickering & Chatto, 2001), vol. 3, 1666–1667, 142.

21John Wilkins was, like Boyle, one of the founding fathers of the Royal Society. And like Henry Oldenburg, he was a secretary of the Royal Society. Henry Oldenburg was secretary of the physical sciences division; John Wilkins was the secretary of the biological sciences division. The Royal Society's website lists all secretaries of the two divisions from 1663 to present at: http://royalsociety.org/about-us/governance/officers/.

23See N. Wilding, ‘The Return of Thomas Salusbury's Life of Galileo (1664)’, British Journal for the History of Science, 41:2 (2008), 241–65.

24T. Salusbury, Mathematical collections and translations …, vol. 1 & 2 (London: printed by William Leybourn, 1661–1665).

25Oldenburg writes: ‘I was but yesterday with Mr Thompson, who uses to acquaint me with the new Books, that come abroad, but he neither then, nor afore, told me any thing of Galilaeo's second Tome: but I shall aske him about it, God willing, the next time I passe that away.’ See Hunter, Clericuzio and Prinzipe, Correspondence of Robert Boyle, vol. 2, 549.

26See ‘Letter 242, Oldenburg to Viviani (28 October 1661)’, in The Correspondence of Henry Oldenburg, edited and translated by A.R. Hall and M.B. Hall, 12 vols (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1966), vol. 1, 443.

27In this paper I will use the following abbreviations to refer to Spinoza's work: PPC = Principles of Cartesian Philosophy (Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae), CM = Metaphysical Thoughts (Cogitata Metaphysica), E= Ethics (Ethica), Ep = Letters (Epistolae), KV = Short Treatise (Korte Verhandeling), TIE = Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect (Tractatus de Intellectus Emendaione), TP = Political Treatise (Tractatus Politicus), TTP = Theological-Political Treatise (Tractatus Theologico-Politicus).

28See ‘Appendix 2: Meyer's Dissertation’, in Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, translated by S. Shirley and introduction and notes by S. Barbone and L. Rice (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 1998), 144–59.

29See letter 81.

30The Traité du monde et de la lumière was published posthumously in 1664.

31See D. Garber, Descartes' Metaphysical Physics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992).

32See letter 8.

33See A. Koyré, Galileo Studies, translated by J. Mepham ( Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1978).

34See Descartes, Œuvres philosophiques, textes établis, présentés et annotés par Ferdinand Alquié, 3 vols (Paris: Classiques Garnier, 1963–1973), vol. 2, 1638–1642, 173.

35See the definition of affecta at E3 def. 3.

36See TIE, 83 and the scholium of proposition 18 of E2.

37See for instance: the third paragraph of the third chapter of his TTP, the scholium of E4p57 and letter 32.

38See letter 6.

39See the preface of E3 and paragraph 6 of chapter 2 of the TP.

40See E. Zilsel, ‘The Genesis of the Concept of Physical Law’, in The Social Origins of Modern Science, edited by D. Raven, W. Krohn, and R.S. Cohen (Dordrecht : Kluwer, 2000), 96–121.

41See Galileo's Letter to the Grand Duchess Christina (1615) and Letter to Castelli (1613) in The Essential Galileo, edited and translated by M.A. Finocchiaro (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 2008), 103–45.

42In his letter 13 to Oldenburg, Spinoza exclusively uses the term ‘the laws of mechanics’ (Leges Mechanicae).

43See chapter 6 of the TTP.

44 A Free Enquiry into the Vulgarly Received Notion of Nature, edited by M. Hunter and E.B. Davis (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996 [1686]).

45See E.B. Davis and M. Hunter, ‘Boyle's Free Enquiry’ in A Free Enquiry, xxiii.

46See A Free Enquiry, 22, 51.

47See EIp29s and KV, I, Cap. VIII and IX.

48See letter 6.

49See P. Steenbakkers, ‘Een vijandige overname: Spinoza over natura naturans en natura naturata’, in Spinoza en de scholastiek, edited by G. Coppens (Leuven: Acco, 2003), 35–52.

50The most important writings on the Spinoza/Boyle correspondence are: C.A. Crommelin, Spinoza's natuurwetenschappelijk denken (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1939); H. Daudin, ‘Spinoza et la science expérimentale: sa discussion de l'expérience de Boyle’, Revue d'histoire des sciences et de leurs applications, PUF, 2:2 Janvier–Avril (1949); A.R. Hall and M.B. Hall, ‘Philosophy and Natural Philosophy: Boyle and Spinoza’, in Mélanges Alexandre Koyré, edited by R. Taton and F. Braudel, 2 vols (Paris: Hermann, 1964), vol. 2, 241–56; E. Yakira, ‘Boyle et Spinoza’, Archives de Philosophie, 51 (1988), 107–24; A. Clericuzio, ‘A Redefinition of Boyle's Chemistry and Corpuscular Philosophy’, Annals of Science, 47 (1990), 561–89; P. Macherey, ‘Spinoza lecteur et critique de Boyle’, Revue du Nord, 77 (1995), 733–74; Clericuzio, Elements, Principles and Corpuscles, 138–42; S. Duffy, ‘The Difference Between Science and Philosophy: The Spinoza-Boyle Controversy Revisited’, Paragraph, 29:2 (2006), 115–38.

51See letter 1.

52See R. Boyle, “Notes for a paper against Spinoza”. The Boyle Collection, Boyle Papers, volume 3, manuscript document, Fols. 102–3 (2 leaves), RB/1/3/18, 1670s–1680s, London, Archive of the Royal Society.

53See letter 13.

54The French translator of the Il Saggiatore, Christiane Chauviré, remarks in her Ph.D dissertation that in chapter 8 of Book 2 of his Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke retakes quite the same analyses of sensible qualities and reproduces exactly the same analyses of heat as in Galileo's Assayer. See C. Barrès-Chauviré, ‘L’ “essayeur de Galilée” (Il saggiatore)', thèse 3e cycle Philosophie: Paris 1, 1975, LX.

55See Galileo, ‘The Assayer’, in Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo, translated with an introduction and notes by S. Drake (New York: Anchor Books, 1957), 217–81.

56See P.R. Anstey, The Philosophy of Robert Boyle (London: Routledge, 2000), 24.

57See S. Sambursky, ‘The Influence of Galileo on Boyle's Philosophy of Science.’ in Actes du Symposium International des Sciences Physiques et Mathématiques dans la Première Moitié du XVIIe Siècle, 16–18 June 1958, Florence/Paris, 1960, 142–46 and R.E.W. Maddison, ‘Galileo and Boyle: A Contrast.’ in Saggi su Galileo Galilei, edited by C. Maccagni, 2 vols (Florence: G.Barbera, 1967), vol. 2, 348–61.

58Robert Boyle wrote his Account of Philaretus during his Minority in 1648 or 1649.

59Isaac Marcombes was the second husband of Madeleine Burlamacchi (1608–1665) who was the daughter of Jean Diodati's sister, Anne Diodati (1578–1634).

60S. Garcia, Élie Diodati: un homme de réseau au service de la cause galiléenne, Thèse de doctorat, Université de Lausanne, 2003, 34.

61The small octavo notebook now comprises 109 folios that contain three folding tables: one calendrical table, a second showing ‘the qualities and combinations, etc., of the four elements’, and a third entitled ‘A Figure of the Construction of the World’, which shows the Ptolemaic universe. See M. Hunter, Boyle: Between God and Science (New Haven and London: Yale University press, 2009), 53.

62See L.M. Prinzipe, ‘Newly Discovered Boyle Manuscripts in the Royal Society Archive. Alchemical Tracts and His Student Notebook’, Notes Rec. R. Soc., London, 49:1 (1995), 49–70.

63See A. Baillet, Vie de Monsieur Descartes (Paris: Éditions de La Table Ronde, 1946), 52–9, 91.

64D.B. Meli, Thinking with Objects: The Transformation of Mechanics in the Seventeenth Century (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2006), 137.

65See Journal tenu par Isaac Beeckman de 1604 à 1634, edited by C. De Waard, tome 3: 1627–34, 223.

66See for instance: R. Tuck, Hobbes (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989) and F. Brandt, Thomas Hobbes's Mechanical Conception of Nature (Copenhagen: Levin & Munksgaard, 1928).

67See D.M. Jesseph, ‘Galileo, Hobbes, and the Book of Nature’, Perspectives on Science, Special Issue: Galileo in Paris, 12:2 (2004), 191–211.

68See Garcia, Élie Diodati, 86.

69See J.M.M. Aler, Catalogus van de bibliotheek der vereniging Het Spinozahuis te Rijnsburg (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1965).

70See E. Curley, “Kissinger, Spinoza, and Genghis Khan”, in The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza, edited by D. Garrett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 315–42.

71See C.D. Andriesse, Huygens: The Man Behind The Principle (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), xi.

72C. Huygens had the Opere di Galileo Galilei (Bologna, 1656) in his library.

73See for example letter 32 (1665) and letter 54 (1674)

74See also TIE 12.

75See Chapter 7 of the first part of The Elements of Law and De cive, III.3.1.

76See for instance: the scholium of E2p18, the explication at the end of E3, the scholium of E4p1, the proofs of E2p19, E2p23, E2p26, E2p47, E3p18 and E3p27.

77See Drake, Discoveries and Opinions, 277.

78Also Gassendi knew Galileo's Assayer. See P. Redondi, ‘Rendez-vous à Arcetri. A propos de la Correspondance entre Gassendi et Galilée’, in Gassendi et la modernité, edited by S. Taussig (Turnhout: Brepols Publishers NV, 2008), 83–104.

79See letter 12 from Spinoza to Lodewijk Meijer, written in 1663.

80See A. Matheron, Individu et communauté chez Spinoza (Paris: Les Éditions de minuit, 1988).

81See P. Redondi, Galileo eretico (Torino: Einaudi, 1983).

82See F. De Buzon and V. Carraud, Descartes et les “Principia” II - Corps et mouvement (Paris: PUF, 1994), 60–1.

83Descartes' letter to Mersenne of the 25th of October 1630.

84See J.R. Armogathe, ‘L'explication physique de l'Eucharistie’ in La nature du monde - Science nouvelle et exégèse au XVIIe siècle (Paris: PUF, 2007), 149–73.

85See C. Adam et P. Tannery (eds.), CEuvres de Descartes (Paris: Cerf, 1897–1913), V, 184.

86See F. Buyse, ‘Le “démasquement” de Descartes par Spinoza dans Les Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae’, Teoria, 2 (2012).

87J.R. Armogathe, ‘La première condamnation des oeuvres de Descartes, d'après des documents inédits aux archives du Saint-Office’, in Nouvelles de la République des Lettres (Napoli : Prismi II, 2001), 103–37.

88See letter 4.

89See letter 14, written in 1663.

90See S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011).

91C. Huygens writes in letter 400, to an unknown individual: ‘An exquisite and simple method for measuring time lapses was brought into use by astronomers about 27 years ago. A weight was hung on a thread and swung back and forth in equal lapses of time. There is no doubt that Galileo was the pioneer of this invention because he was the first to mention the isochronism of these oscillations. I started to concentrate on how these oscillations could be made persistent and the effort of counting be eliminated, so that it would be apt to measure any lapse of time one wishes to measure. In the beginning of this year 1657 I achieved both goals with the invention of a new clock of which I will now describe the composition and functioning.’

92See letter 30.

93According to Martial Gueroult (‘La physique des corps et du Corps humain’, in Spinoza II – l'âme (Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1974), 143–89. ), Spinoza's simplest bodies (corpora simplicissima) should be conceived as single pendulums, and the other bodies as compound pendulums. This hypothesis has been severely criticized by Gilles Deleuze (Cours Vincennes: Infini actuel-éternité, confrontation avec le commentaire de Guéroult - Logique des relations (10/03/1981) at www.deleuze.com), according to whom Spinoza's simplest bodies should not be conceived as oscillating pieces of matter but as differentials.

94See letter 32.

95See chapters 1 and 6 of part I of the KV.

96A. Clericuzio, Elements, Principles and Corpuscles, 138–43.

97A. Gabbey, ‘Spinoza and Mechanical Philosophy’, Conference on Mechanics and Natural Philosophy, Grenoble, 17–19 November 2005.

98See letter 6.

99See proposition 35 and 41 of E2.

100See letter 13.

101Spinoza here applies the terminology: ‘experientia vaga’ and ‘experimentum’. He uses the same terminology in his Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect. There he defines ‘casual experience’ (experientia vaga) as ‘experience that is not determined by intellect, but is so called because it chances thus to occur, and we have experienced nothing else that contradicts it, so that it remains in our minds unchallenged’. Spinoza defines ‘experientia vaga’ also in Scholium 2 of E2p40: ‘From individual objects presented to us through the senses in a fragmentary (mutilate) and confused manner without any intellectual order [see Cor.Pr. 29, II]; and therefore I call such perceptions “knowledge from casual experience”.’ P.F. Moreau remarked that we already find the distinction between experientia and experimentum in the dispute between P. Grassi and Galileo. See J.P. Moreau, Spinoza - L'expérience et l'éternité. (Paris: PUF, 1994), 264.

102See letter 6.

103See letter 16.

104See E.J. Dijksterhuis, Clio's stiefkind, edited by K. van Berkel (Amsterdam: Uitgeverij Bert Bakker, 1990), 169–92.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 185.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.