173
Views
1
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Validity and Interpretation

Pages 247-264 | Received 01 May 2008, Accepted 01 Aug 2008, Published online: 23 Jun 2009
 

Abstract

This paper claims that there is a plausible sense in which validity is a matter of truth preservation relative to interpretations of the sentences that occur in an argument, although it is not the sense one might have in mind. §1 outlines three independent problems: the first is the paradox of the sorites, the second concerns the fallacy of equivocation, and the third arises in connection with the standard treatment of indexicals. §2 elucidates the claim about validity, while §§3–5 show how the three problems outlined can be handled in accordance with it. §6 explains how the claim squares with the traditional idea that validity is related to formality, and in particular with a broadly accepted definition based on that idea, the model-theoretic definition of logical consequence. Unlike other works on the subject, this paper does not focus on necessity. It is not its intention to provide a characterization of necessity that conforms to some ideal of rigour or to some pre-theoretical understanding of validity. What follows can be taken as conditional on the assumption that such a characterization can be provided.

Notes

1Logic textbooks don't help much in this sense. For example, Copi Citation1986: 113] can hardly be regarded as an explanation. The fallacy of equivocation is no isolated case. Usually logic textbooks introduce fallacies by drawing on a corpus of traditional examples accompanied by standard comments. But in many cases it is not clear from those examples or comments what is wrong with the argument.

2Fogelin and Sinnott-Armstrong Citation2001: 367] provide an account of this kind. Note that it is not essential to the account that the alleged real argument is defined in terms of propositions. Any set of entities—such as syntactic constructs—that ensures disambiguation will do.

3The same trouble arises if the fallacy is described in terms of a plurality of arguments disguised as a single one, as in Kirwan Citation1979 or in Woods and Walton Citation1979.

4The standard definition goes back to Kaplan Citation1977. There, ‘context’ is used instead of ‘index’. To avoid ambiguity, here ‘context’ is used only as a non-technical term, to refer to a possibly concrete situation in which a sentence or a set of sentences can be used. Predelli Citation2005: 83] and Braun Citation2001: §3.3] regard the standard definition as ‘intuitive’.

5Here ‘non-univocal’ is not to be read as synonymous with ‘equivocal’. Equivocality entails non-univocality, but is not entailed by it. The two cases considered involve a non-univocal use of a word, yet it seems incorrect to call that use equivocal. The problem surfaces in Kaplan Citation1989: 586–7]. Takashi Yagisawa is among the few who recognize its force, see Yagisawa Citation1993: 471–4].

6As far as vague predicates are concerned, admissibility is understood along the lines suggested in Fine Citation1975.

7Valuations differ from structures in the same way. The only respect in which valuations, unlike interpretations, resemble structures is that they are defined for the whole language rather than for single sentences.

8That is done in Iacona [forthcoming] (a)].

9See Williamson Citation1994: 147–8], Keefe Citation2000: §3], and Varzi Citation2007.

10According to Church Citation1942, this is part of the very definition of the fallacy.

11Yagisawa Citation1993: 483] treats UC as a pragmatic principle that does not belong to logic.

12The material of this section is drawn from Iacona [forthcoming (b)], which focuses on arguments affected by context-sensitivity.

13As noted by Timothy Smiley Citation1982/3.

14The expression ‘adequate formalization’ is used in Sainsbury Citation1991.

15This is essentially the point made by Sainsbury Citation1991: 63], when he says that an adequate formalization must preserve what the sentences in the argument say.

16LC goes back to Tarski Citation1936.

17As it emerges from the debate generated by Etchemendy Citation1990. To use Etchemendy's terminology, LC is ‘interpretational’, while VI and FVI are ‘representational’ (at least if it is assumed that invariance of linguistic meaning suffices for representationality).

18An argument along these lines was first provided in Kreisel Citation1967. See also Hanson Citation1997 and Gómez-Torrente Citation2006.

19I should like to thank Mario Gómez-Torrente, Diego Marconi and three anonymous referees for some valuable remarks that helped me to improve the paper.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 94.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.