849
Views
6
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Right Action as Virtuous Action

ORCID Icon
Pages 241-254 | Received 12 Sep 2016, Published online: 24 Jul 2017
 

ABSTRACT

I argue in favour of the central claim of virtue-ethical accounts of right action: that right action is virtuous action. First, I disambiguate this claim and argue for a specific interpretation of it. Second, I provide reasons to prefer target-centred over both agent-centred and motive-centred accounts of virtuous action. Third, I argue that an action is right if, only if, and because it is overall virtuous. Finally, I respond to important arguments to the contrary.

Notes

1 Motive-centred theorists may object to the target-centred account's implication that agents may perform right actions by accident. However, although agents do not merit praise for accidentally doing the right thing, it remains plausible that one can do the right thing for the wrong reason, at least on some occasions (see Van Zyl [Citation2009] for an excellent discussion of accidental rightness). In addition, it is possible for target-centred accounts to allow that an agent's motives are relevant to the rightness of her action in some contexts [Swanton Citation2003: 231; Van Zyl Citation2014: 122–4].

2 The qualification ‘non-trivial’ allows for the possibility that virtuous agents always aim to act well. Since acting well is amorphous, it may not distort the variety of ends of action. I do not mean that this end is trivial in all philosophical contexts.

3 There are additional reasons to prefer VE over consequentialisms. First, since some constitutive ends of virtue are agent-relative—e.g. those of prudence and filial piety—VE is superior in allowing for ultimate, agent-relative reasons for action. Second, consequentialist accounts require a base theory of value that is independent of aretaic notions, such as hedonism, preference satisfaction, or objective list theory. For a persuasive argument that such theories are implausible, see Swanton [Citation2003: ch. 2].

4 RPV = Rightness (is) Prior (to) Virtuousness. It is unclear whether Crisp accepts RPV but, unless he does, he cannot conclude that speaking out is unjust from the premises that it is wrong and within the sphere of justice.

5 For a controversial example, Jeffrey Reiman [Citation2002] argues that capital punishment is just in some circumstances but is never required by justice.

6 It does follow if the reciprocity of the virtues is assumed. However, the reciprocity of the virtues is a claim that is almost always supported by something like the assumption that each virtue issues in nothing but right conduct. If this is how one supports the reciprocity of the virtues, it is circular reasoning to use the reciprocity of the virtues as support for the claim that each virtue issues in nothing but right conduct.

7 I thank two anonymous referees and Stephen Hetherington for helpful comments and suggestions.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 94.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.