2,336
Views
3
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
SPECIAL ISSUE - Epistemic Injustice and Education

Trust, distrust, and testimonial injustice

ORCID Icon &
Pages 290-300 | Received 14 Sep 2021, Accepted 12 Jan 2022, Published online: 08 Apr 2022

Abstract

This essay investigates an underappreciated way in which trust and testimonial injustice are closely connected. Credibility deficit and credibility excess cases both (in their own distinctive ways) contribute to a speaker’s being harmed in her capacity a knower. But moreover, as we will show—by using the tools of a performance-theoretic framework—both credibility deficit and credibility excess cases also feature incompetent trusting on the part of the hearer. That is, credibility deficit and excess cases are shown to manifest qualities of thinkers that are inconducive to trust’s being reliably fulfilled. What this implies is an interesting result about testimonial injustice: to the extent that we want to mitigate against testimonial injustice—one promising way to do so will be to target incompetent trusting of the sort that underlies it. We conclude by outlining and defending what we take to be a promising substantive version of such a mitigation strategy, one which is centred around the cultivation of higher-order trusting competences.

1. Introduction

Epistemic injustice has—since Miranda Fricker’s (Citation2007) landmark work on the topic—become increasingly well understood as its own genus of epistemic harm, with testimonial injustice as a species of particular interest for social epistemologists.Footnote1 Testimonial injustice is generally taken to occur when a speaker’s testimony is not given the level of credence it deserves by a prejudiced hearer, and the result is that the speaker is unable to share what she knows.

The more we learn about the prevalence of testimonial injustice and its damaging effects, the more important it becomes to know how to best address it.Footnote2 Part of what makes this so difficult to combat is that the mechanisms driving testimonial injustice are often sourced in biases of which we are generally unaware.Footnote3 This paper explores one specific and largely unexploredFootnote4 strategy for combatting epistemic injustice, by focusing on the ways in which it is generated by defective ways of trusting. The central line we want to advance is that by becoming a more skilled truster—that is, by developing our trust-relevant abilities and, crucially, better understanding their limits—we can at the same time help to minimize our contributions to epistemic injustice.

Here is the plan: §2 describes two faces of epistemic injustice, credibility deficit and (more controversially) credibility excess, and explores how each contributes to harming a testifier in her capacity as a knower. §3 then discusses trust as an attitude with its own constitutive normativity, with a focus on what competent (and incompetent) trusting involves. §4 shows how credibility deficit and credibility excess fail to constitute competent trusting for different reasons, and §5 suggests strategies for mitigating testimonial injustice by targeting its sources in incompetent trusting.

2. Testimonial injustice

On Fricker’s (Citation2007) account, testimonial injustice occurs when a speaker is harmed in her capacity as a knowerFootnote5 by receiving an unfair deficit of credibility from a hearer due to prejudice on the hearers’ part. Our prejudicial dysfunctions in our testimonial practice fall into broadly two categories. Firstly, prejudice can result in the speaker receiving more credibility than she otherwise would have—credibility excess—or it results in her receiving less credibility than she otherwise would have—credibility deficit.

To make these ideas concrete, consider Fricker’s example of a speaker’s accent which carries a social charge that affects how the hearer perceives the speaker, e.g. it indicates—given background assumptions on the part of the hearer—a certain class or educational background. It also carries an epistemic charge; it can have a significant impact as to how much credibility is afforded to the speaker, as a prejudice towards someone’s accent may inflate or deflate the credibility of the speaker, in turn causing the hearer to miss out on knowledge.

A central example of testimonial injustice Fricker appeals to is Harper Lee’s To Kill a Mockingbird, where Tom Robinson, who is a black man on trial after being falsely accused of raping a white woman, is initially disbelieved by the prejudiced jury.

At first glance, credibility excess (e.g. imagine giving undue credibility on a specialized health matter to a GP that outstrips actual expertise, generating on them an undue burden) both seem like cases of testimonial injustice, broadly construed; at least, it might seem initially unprincipled to restrict the category of testimonial injustice to credibility deficit cases. Though, on this point Fricker holds firm. First, she holds that whilst some cases of credibility excess may be cases of injustice with regards to distributive unfairness (i.e. someone has more of their fair share of the good), credibility is not—like wealth or healthcare for example—a good which belongs within the distributive model of justice. Accordingly, in cases of credibility deficit, the injustice suffered by the hearer should not be characterized as a failure to receive one’s share of the good, as this would fail to capture how the speaker is wronged. Instead, Fricker maintains, testimonial injustice of a philosophically interesting sort is a distinctively epistemic injustice, viz., a kind of injustice in which someone is wronged specifically in their capacity as a knower. Credibility deficit can fit this definition, however, credibility excess does not. As she summarises:

[…] while credibility excess may (unusually) be disadvantageous in various ways, it does not undermine, insult, or otherwise withhold proper respect for the speaker qua subject of knowledge; so in itself it does her no epistemic injustice, and a fortiori no testimonial injustice. (2007, 20)

One notable line of resistance on this point is due to José Medina (Citation2011). As Medina sees it, Fricker’s restriction of testimonial injustice to credibility deficit cases is problematic because credibility judgements, deficits and excesses—are implicitly comparative and contrasting. Epistemic injustices, according to Medina, are produced principally by two intrinsically interrelated phenomena: a lack of recognition (credibility deficit) and epistemic privilege (credibility excess). The excess of epistemic privilege enjoyed by some constitutes, at the same time, an injustice that is directly related to the credibility deficits of others.Footnote6

Medina captures this intrinsically relational way of thinking about credibility deficit/excess by (among other things) drawing from scientific studies which show that, e.g. students in American universities automatically tend to give less credibility than otherwise to teachers who are (either) female, non-white, and/or with a foreign accent. The credibility excess that is afforded to male, white, native-speaking, heterosexual teachers, as evidenced by such studies, positively correlated with the credibility deficits of the teachers who are not members of this group.

For our own purposes, we can remain neutral on the crux of the dispute between Fricker and Medina. What is of relevance going forward is that credibility deficit and credibility excess both plausibly contribute to testimonial harm, even if only the former (as Fricker submits and Medina denies) distinctively constitutes that harm.

3. Competent trusting

We’ll consider in the next section how both credibility excess and credibility deficit bear important connections to trust. But in order to get these connections in proper view, it will be helpful first to clarify trust’s constituent normativity. Doing this will shed light on what good (and bad) trusting involves, and eventually, how testimonial injustice manifests the latter.

With this in mind—and drawing from the performance normativity frameworkFootnote7 (PNF) that has gained traction in epistemology and elsewhere as a framework for organising performance evaluations—consider that any performance (athletic performance, doxastic, etc.) with an aim can be evaluated along three distinct dimensions. First, we can ask did the performance succeed in attaining its aim?; second (and regardless of how we answer the first question) we may ask: was the performance competent? And third, we can ask whether the performance was apt—viz., successful because competent.

Take, for an illustrative case, the performance of an archer firing a shot at a target. If (and only if) the shot actually hits the target, it is successful; that is, it succeeds in attaining the aim internal to the performance of archery. Even if it misses, though, the shot might still be competent; it is competent if only if the shot manifests a form that reliably enough (in appropriate circumstances) would issue in success. Just as a shot can be successful while not being competent, a shot can be competent without being successful (e.g. you might miss the target, having used reliable form, due to dumb luck). Aptness, on the PNF model, demands not just success and competence, but also that the success be because of the competence; only a shot that is successful because competent (and not merely successful and competentFootnote8) is an apt shot.

The three distinct dimensions of performance evaluation according to PNF, success, competence, and aptness, apply not only to athletic performances like shooting at an archery target, but also to any performance-type with an aim that is internal to that kind of endeavour of which that performance is an instance. The most influential application of PNF in contemporary philosophy is in epistemology (and particularly in virtue epistemologyFootnote9), where—with respect to the performance of belief, specifically—success, competence, and aptness line up neatly with truth (i.e. successful belief), justification (competent belief) and knowledge (i.e. apt belief).

As one of us has argued elsewhere,Footnote10 some of the key philosophical payoffs that virtue epistemologists have enjoyed by applying PNF to ‘belief’, qua performance, also extend, mutatis mutandis, to trust—and in particular, to what philosophers of trust call three-place trust (S trusts X to take care of something Y, as opposed to two-place trust, e.g. S trusts X).Footnote11 The central idea here is as follows. Just as a belief ‘misses its mark’ and is not successful (even if it’s well justified, rational, etc.) if the target belief is false, likewise, three-place trust (hereafter, ‘trust’) has (even if perfectly reasonable, etc.) missed its mark if the trustee does not in fact take care of things as entrusted to. For example, there is a sense in which your trusting your cousin to keep a secret is simply not successful if your cousin spills the beans. Of course, if your cousin had never spilled the beans before and was in fact a very reliable person generally, then your trusting them with the secret might have been competent in a way that, say, trusting a child would have not been. Trusting your cousin and those with a similar responsibility profile ordinarily enough results in your trust not being betrayed. Whereas, trusting a child does not reliably enough end up in your trust not being betrayed, even if a child on occasion might successfully fulfil the trust you place in them.

The fact that competent trust and successful trust can come apart in both directions parallels the way that competent and successful belief can come apart in both directions (e.g. true beliefs can be unjustified/incompetently formed, and false beliefs can be justified/competently formed). Moreover, just as you can have a successful belief (true) that is apt—viz., when the belief’s correctness manifests a belief-forming competence—likewise, your trusting someone to φ can also be apt; this will be whenever successful trust manifests (i.e. is because of) a competence to trust successfully reliably enough.

What might such a trust-relevant competence look like? It falls out of the PNF framework that a trust competence will be a disposition to trust successfully (i.e. to have the trustee take care of things as entrusted) reliably enough. (Compare: an epistemic competence is a competence to attain epistemic success, viz., true beliefs, reliably enough). But all of this just invites the further question: what kind of qualities of a truster will actually dispose her to reliably—when she trusts someone with something—have her trust fulfilled as opposed to betrayed?

We can gain some traction here, we suggest, by using characteristic features of trusting incompetence as a reference point for getting a grip on what the positive features of a trusting competence might involve. Three salient personal qualities that can easily lead a truster to unsuccessful trust are the following. First, one might have an overly naïve or cynical perspective on others’ abilities and intentions, which can lead the truster to overestimate or underestimate the trustee’s competence or good will in a particular trust exchange. In the former case, one might, trust a complete stranger (perhaps a teenager) to invest a large amount of money for them. In the latter case, one might, for example, assume that all (or a some large subset of all) individuals are ‘selfish’ and as a result disproportionately refrain from trusting even reliable and trustworthy individuals with basic tasks or to relay information.

A second kind of disposition that might too often lead one away from successful trust is introspective. Some individuals, due to distortions they have in their introspective capacities, lack an accurate view of themselves that leads them to take on unnecessary risks of betrayal. To take an example from recent film, Jimmy Hoffa’s character, as portrayed by Al Pacino in Martin Scorsese’s The Irishman, was ultimately betrayed by a mafia group which he refused (even given ample warnings) to believe would ever betray him. His refusal to believe this, however, was not grounded in any attitudes he had about the mafia or their intentions, per se, but due to a misconception of his own (in)vulnerability that was grounded in an inflated sense of his own importance—both generally, and to the mafia.

A third quality of character that can easily increase one’s risk of betrayal is a distorted perception not of (i) others’ abilities or intentions (e.g. Robinson’s Jury); or (ii) of one’s own value or worth (Hoffa’s character), but rather (iii) of the gains that betrayal would afford to the trustee and the felicity by which it could be achieved. A poor calibration on this score could result in disproportionately incentivising such betrayals, e.g. by too often entrusting high-value information with little expected payoffs and where betrayal could not easily enough be detected.

The foregoing three varieties of trusting incompetence point to at least three distinct qualities we can reasonably expect will contribute to competent trusting—viz., to manifesting dispositions that reliably (enough) issue in successful as opposed to betrayed trust. These qualities involve a suitable reliability threshold when it comes to assessing: (a) others’ abilities and intentions; (b) oneself, including one’s values and beliefs; and (c) expected gains by (and felicity of) betrayal. Reliability along these three dimensions can be expected to contribute to one’s being a competent rather than an incompetent truster (even if not it is not exhaustive of it) given the conduciveness of reliability along these dimensions to successful trust.

4. Credibility deficit and excess as incompetent trusting

Let’s now bring the discussions from §§2 to 3 together. We’ve seen from Fricker and Medina that both credibility deficit as well as credibility excess contribute in their own ways to testimonial injustice, and this is the case regardless of whether credibility excess (as Medina maintains and Fricker denies) itself actually constitutes testimonial injustice.

In this section, what we want to suggest is that both credibility deficit as well as credibility excess not only contribute to testimonial injustice, but also that they constitute manifestations (respectively) of incompetent trusting, and that this can be shown (in the case of both credibility deficit and credibility excess) with references to one or more of the three dimensions of competent/incompetent trusting we considered in §2.

Let’s begin with credibility deficit, using Fricker’s illustrative Tom Robinson case from To Kill a Mockingbird) as a reference point. Notice, for starters, that in this example, the jury badly misjudges both Tom Robinson’s abilities and his intentions to communicate the truth. This misjudging, which derives from the jury’s identity prejudice leads the jury not towards, but away from, trusting successfully. To draw an analogy with an epistemic case involving perception: if (due to a prejudice against the designers of a building) one misjudged their abilities and intentions such that they anticipated incompetence and deceptiveness, one might withhold judgment on whether, for example, what they are seeing is what it looks like, as opposed to trusting their senses, which would have delivered the truth.

Additionally—and apart from these prejudiced beliefs the jury holds about the hearer—the jury’s own introspective defects are plausibly part of the problem as well. Just as, e.g. Jimmy Hoffa’s distorted view of his value blocked him from appreciating his own vulnerability to betrayal, likewise, Robinson’s jury’s distorted view of their own methods of belief forming (e.g. they think they are forming beliefs on the basis of evidence, but they lack access to the fact that they are not) blocks them from giving the credibility to the speaker that would typically be necessary to have enabled trust in the first place.

In the case of credibility excess, consider how misjudging ability and intention can also play a structurally similar (albeit, inverse) kind of role in leading to the betrayal of trust. In our example case, the jury plausibly begins with a bias in favour of Bob and Mayella Ewell, who are members of a privileged racial group, as competent and sincere testifiers. And such judgment, which (at least, plausibly, on the story) derives from identity prejudice that substantially benefits these testifiers, hinders the jury’s capacity to from trust successfully. In short, their prejudiced inflation of the Ewell’s aptitude and integrity contributes in a direct way toward the jury’s betrayal of the trust that is so disproportionately placed in them.

Likewise, the jury’s own introspective defects plausibly compound their capacity to avoid betrayal by the Ewell’s. In particular, their distorted view of their own methods of belief forming (e.g. they are oblivious to the way their own view of themselves in connection with the Ewells is artificially inflating their assessments of how credible the Ewells are) blocks them from giving due consideration to the abundant counterevidence to this testimony that they encounter at the trial.

And thirdly, in connection with credibility excess, it’s worth highlighting that the jurors’ identity prejudice benefiting the testifiers leaves the jurors inappropriately attentive to the extent to which the Ewells, in this case, stand to both gain substantially through betrayal and that they can achieve this highly beneficial aim without much risk of detection.

In sum, then, the takeaway lesson from this section can be summarised as follows: credibility deficit and credibility excess line up in important ways not only with testimonial injustice but also with incompetent trusting. That is, not only (as discussed in §2) do both kinds of credibility distortions contribute to testimonial injustice, by promoting (and in the case of credibility deficit, by additionally constituting) the harming of a testifier in her capacity as a knower; but further, both credibility deficit and credibility excess cases feature (in different ways) several of the key markers of incompetent trusting (i.e. features of trusters that dispose them away from attaining successful trust), which were are plainly manifest in both cases of credibility deficit and credibility excess.

What this all points to is that—to the extent we want to mitigate against testimonial injustice—one promising strategy for doing so would be an indirect one: in short, to target the incompetent trusting. And thinking about targeting testimonial injustice this way—e.g. through the route of targeting incompetent trusting—comes with a pleasing advantage: there is, from within the PNF framework, already a helpful structure in place for organising this kind of strategy, one that involves the development of metacompetences, that is, second-order competences to (to a first approximation) suitably regulate one’s exercise of first-order competences.Footnote12 Let’s turn now to getting this positive idea in view.

5. Trust, metacompetence, and mitigation of testimonial injustice

Even those who have the competence to do something reliably might at the same time have a poor perspective on the limits of their own competence. To take a familiar example from Ernest Sosa (Citation2015), suppose a huntress, Diana, is more competent than she thinks; she fires an arrow at a target in the twilight fog from a considerable distance and hits it. Diana might think her shot is lucky; but she’s wrong, and this is because she underestimates how reliable she is when firing a shot in those conditions. When firing in those conditions, not easily would she have missed.

As Sosa describes the case, the shot is apt—it is successful because competent. However, even so, there is a sense in which Diana’s shot has room for improvement, when we evaluate it as a performance. After all, Diana’s shot, though apt, could easily have been inapt. Even though she has an impressive competence to shoot arrows at targets (in those conditions) reliably, she lacks the ability to discern whether she is within, our outside, the limits within which she’d be suitably reliable to take have taken the shot. Given this poor perspective, she very easily would have shot beyond her competence in this case and so very easily would have shot inaptly.

A higher zone of performance quality lacks this feature through better risk management. Compare: (i) a shot that is apt, but which could easily have been inapt; with (ii) a shot which is apt, but wouldn’t easily have been inapt. Whereas Diana’s shot falls into the former category, we can imagine the following kind of performance falling into the latter category: a shot that is not only apt (successful because competence) but also such that not easily would the individual—say Diana*—have taken the shot were it have been inapt.

What distinguishes Diana from Diana* is not archery skills so much as it is the capacity to govern those skills through a skilled assessment of their limits. Within performance-theoretic virtue epistemology, the term ‘metacompetence’ is used to describe these kinds of ‘higher-order’ or ‘reflective’ dispositions thinkers have to regulate their first-order dispositions.Footnote13 A meta-competence, in a given domain of endeavour, D, is a competence to reliably enough attain not merely the first-order D-aim, but to attain the further aim of aptly attaining the D-aim, reliably enough (see, e.g. Carter, Citation2019, §9; Sosa, Citation2015, p. 69). It is in virtue of possessing this kind of higher-order competence, for example, that Diana* (but not Diana) will refrain from shooting when just a bit too far outside the threshold from which, if she took the shot, it would be apt; whereas both Diana and Diana* are competent at shooting arrows, only Diana* has a competent view of her own competence, and so understands where the limits of this competence lie; and this understanding in turn regulates when she will decide to shoot as opposed to forbear.

Transposing things now to the arena of trust, specifically: the distinction between a trust competence and a trusting metacompetence is as follows. Whereas the former involves the disposition to trust successfully reliably enough (i.e. to trust such that the trustee takes care of things—including providing the truth, in the epistemic case—as entrusted) when one tries in appropriate conditions, the latter involves a disposition to trust aptly reliably enough. Just as Diana*, but not Diana, understood the limits of her own competence in light of the relevant meta-competence she has to assess her own archery prowess, an epistemic agent possesses the kind of metacompetence that matters for trust when she can reliably recognises the limits of her competence to trust successfully reliably enough.

What the possession of such a metacompetence in the archery versus trust cases involves, of course, is entirely different. The former involves good risk assessment abilities when it comes to assessing how one’s reliability at hitting a target is sensitive to different kinds of archery performance conditions (e.g. high winds, distance from target, lighting conditions, etc.), as well as a capacity to assess which kinds of performance-relevant conditions are the ones that actually obtain.

Trusting metacompetence, on the other hand, involves good risk assessment abilities when it comes to assessing how one’s reliability at trusting successfully is sensitive to various kinds of factors, as well as a capacity to assess when such factors obtain. We’ve already seen, in §3, that whether one is reliable (or unreliable) at trusting successfully depends on how well one performs along (at least) three salient dimensions: at assessing (a) others abilities and intentions; (b) oneself, including one’s values and beliefs; and (c) expected gains by (and felicity of) betrayal on the part of the trustee. Whereas a competent truster simply needs to be reliable along these dimensions—this will de facto lead her to trust successfully reliably enough—a meta-competent truster will need to be able to reliably assess how she measures up vis-à-vis (a–c), and what the relevant situation one finds oneself in demands of her vis-à-vis (a–c).

We’re now in a position to connect the foregoing discussion of trusting metacompetence with testimonial injustice. Given that credibility deficit and excess cases are both cases of incompetent trusting (from §3), one entirely straightforward way to mitigate against testimonial injustice will be to simply become more competent at trusting—that is, to develop those qualities (e.g. a–c) in virtue of which one will be disposed to trust successfully reliably enough.

But this just raises the question—what can we do to mitigate testimonial injustice if we’re already (in some ways) incompetent along (a–c); or, put another way, suppose we are not already functioning reliably along (a–c). How should we then mitigate against epistemic injustice in the non-ideal scenario where we find ourselves regularly in social communication with others (including potentially vulnerable or traditionally marginalised parties) while at the same time lacking one or more dimensions of reliability along (a–c)?

It is here where we think a focus on trust-relevant metacompetences has special value as a strategy for mitigating testimonial injustice. Suppose, for example, that Jay is a juror on Robinson’s case and—like the rest of the jurors—Jay’s identity prejudices affect how he views both Tom’s and the Ewells’ abilities as well as their intentions (respectively) to tell the truth on the issue of the crime at hand. This quality of Jay’s, of course, contributes to making him incompetent as a receiver of court testimony; when receiving such testimony, this quality too easily leads him away from trusting successfully, e.g. by leading him to have his trust betrayed (as it is) by the Ewells as well as preventing him from placing trust (which would not have been betrayed) in Tom’s word.

Now, Let Jay* be just like Jay in so far as Jay* also harbours identity prejudices that draw him towards a distorted view of both Tom’s and the Ewells’ abilities as well as their intentions. But stipulate that Jay*, unlike Jay, has worked to better cultivate an understanding of his shortcomings as a truster when it comes to accepting others’ capacities to testify competently and sincerely. He realises, e.g. through reflection, education, and therapy, etc., that he is subject to identity prejudices that are deeply seated in him, due to his upbringing.

As a result, Jay* has a competent view of his own reliability (and indeed, unreliability) when it comes to assessing the court testimony and Jay does not. Unfortunately, this difference between Jay* and Jay in terms of trusting metacompetence does not simply cause Jay* to not be drawn to afford more credibility to the Ewells than to Tom. He, like Jay, still finds himself pulled in the direction of accepting what the Ewells are saying and rejecting what Tom is saying.Footnote14

While the metacompetence he possesses does not afford Jay* the ability to not be drawn in the direction he is, it does afford him the power to appreciate this limitation, and through this appreciation, to empower himself to avoid mistakes in both directions when it comes to his response to the Ewells and Tom, respectively. Unlike Jay, Jay* will not simply trust the Ewells say and distrust what Tom says even though doing so aligns exactly with his prejudice-driven inclinations (as it does with Jay’s).

Here it will be helpful to briefly draw an analogy with visual-perceptual competence and metacompetence; suppose you are afflicted with a form of red–green colour blindness that prevents you from reliably identifying red things as red and green things as green. The matter of how you interact with the red- and green-coloured world around you will be a function not only of the colour-blindness but also, importantly, of the extent to which you recognise it. Oblivious to the affliction, you will make judgments in line with your perceptually incompetent inclinations to find green things red and red things green, etc. However, if you understand the limits of your visual competences, you will be positioned to react differently to apparent red and apparent green, e.g. by agnosticism in some cases, and in others, to let other kinds of evidence you have about the colour you appear to see override what your senses seem to tell you.

By parity of reasoning, Jay* (but not Jay), is positioned so as to recognise the limits of his (in)competence, when it comes to trust in connection with the Ewells and Tom, and through this recognition, is better positioned to resist the inclinations he has to simply (like one with red-green colour blindness but who is unaware of this) assent to these inclinations.

To be clear, the possession of metacompetence, through the acquisition of a better understanding of one’s competence, doesn’t simply cause one to resist the relevant inclinations that align with one’s (first-order) incompetence. (Compare: an intellectually vicious individual, even aware of red-green colourblindness, might simply and dogmatically assent to red and green appearances nonetheless, as a result of a more general intellectual viciousness). It does, however, better position a thinker to do so, and so to trust (or refrain from doing so) against the kinds of inclinations that would result in injust credibility deficit and excess. By working to cultivate not only competences in trusting, but metacompetences to better appreciate the limits of our trusting reliably, we position ourselves to refrain from contributing to testimonial injustices even in circumstances where our trusting would otherwise be incompetent in such a way that would have likely brought it about. Whether we in fact do as these metacompetences position us to do will, however—and analogously with the perceptual case—depend importantly on what other kinds of virtues (and vices) we have.

7. Concluding remarks

Testimonial injustice is prevalent and harmful, and there are a range of ways (epistemic, moral, and political) we might legitimately try to combat it.Footnote15 This essay has explored just one very specific way. By appreciating how testimonial injustice is sourced in trusting incompetence, we equip ourselves with resource to tackle testimonial injustice from within the kind of framework in which the management and regulation of other kinds of incompetences has been fruitfully explored.Footnote16

Additional information

Funding

This work was supported by The Leverhulme Trust (Grant number: RPG-2019-302).

Notes on contributors

J. Adam Carter

J Adam Carter is a Reader in Epistemology and deputy director of the COGITO Epistemology Research Centre at the University of Glasgow. His latest book is Autonomous Knowledge (2022), with Oxford University Press.

Daniella Meehan

Daniela Meehan is a PhD Candidate in Philosophy at the University of Glasgow, working mainly in social epistemology, virtue and vice epistemology, and on epistemic blame.

Notes

1 See, for example, Kidd, Medina, and Pohlhaus (Citation2017), Maitra (Citation2010), Wanderer (Citation2012, Citation2017); Pohlhaus Jr (Citation2014), Medina (Citation2011, Citation2013, Citation2017); McKinnon (Citation2016), Coady (Citation2017), Bondy (Citation2010), Luzzi (Citation2016), and Battaly (Citation2017).

2 See, in particular, the essays in Sherman and Goguen (Citation2019).

3 For some recent discussions of epistemic injustice and bias, see, e.g., Goguen (Citation2016) and Peet (Citation2017).

4 For an important though different take on the relationship between epistemic and trust than we are pursuing here, see Origgi (Citation2012).

5 Both species of epistemic injustice, testimonial and hermeneutical, involve one’s being harmed in her capacity as a knower, with the latter species being due to unfair deprivation of concepts necessary for the expression of one’s ideas. For some representative recent discussions, beyond Fricker’s own, see, e.g., Beeby (Citation2011), Crerar (Citation2016), Medina (Citation2012), and Simion (forthcoming).

6 For some other discussions of credibility excess, see, e.g., Emmalon Davis’s (Citation2016) discussion of typecasting/spokesperson cases Hypatia paper and Jennifer Lackey’s (Citation2020) discussion of false confessions.

7 The performance normativity framework has been pioneered in work by Ernest Sosa (Citation2007, Citation2010, Citation2015, Citation2017), both as a framework for evaluating performances in general, and epistemic performances in particular. For further discussion, see, e.g., the essays in Fernandez (ed.) (Citation2016), as well as Carter (Citation2016, Citation2019, Citation2020a,Citationb, forthcoming) and Kelp et al. (Citation2020).

8 An example of a performance that is successful and competent but not apt is the following: suppose you fire a shot from reliable form, which is blown off target due to a surprise gust of wind—and then—blown back on course due to a second fortuitous gust of wind, such that it hits the target. This kind of shot is competent, and it is also successful, but the success is not because of the competence, but because of luck. For discussion of this and similar cases, see, e.g., Sosa (Citation2010) and Pritchard (Citation2012, Citation2015).

9 See, along with Sosa, Greco (Citation2003, Citation2009, Citation2010, Citation2012), Turri (Citation2011, Citation2016) and Zagzebski (Citation1996).

10 See Carter (Citation2019, Citation2020a).

11 For a discussion of this difference, see, e.g., Holton (Citation1994) and McLeod (Citation2015).

12 It is worth registering that while Fricker focuses on the individual virtue of testimonial justice as a response to both testimonial and hermeneutical epistemic injustice, Anderson (Citation2012) argues for a systematic perspective - that some epistemic harms must be corrected at a collective, structural level. Similar proposals have been put forth by Maitra (Citation2010), Langton (Citation2010) and others. Langton raises concerns as to whether individual efforts (in the form of individual virtues) can remedy the structural problem of hermeneutical injustice, which is notably both an individual and structural vice. Finally, Ishani Maitra questions whether we should accept the asymmetry between Fricker’s understanding of testimonial injustice as a matter of individual identity prejudice and hermeneutical injustice as a matter of structural identity prejudice. She argues that both kinds of prejudice can contribute to each kind of epistemic injustice but with varying degrees.

13 For other philosophical approaches to metacognition outside of virtue epistemology specifically, see for example Proust (Citation2013) and Morton (Citation2012).

14 Compare here with a similar case familiar from the assertion literature, which is Lackey’s (Citation2008) RACIST JUROR case. In this case, a racist juror votes and asserts in accordance with what they know the evidence requires, while at the same time, harbouring private beliefs that align with racism.

15 See especially Sherman and Goguen (2019) as well as Meehan (Citation2020).

16 Carter’s work on this paper is part of the ‘A Virtue Epistemology of Trust’ (#RPG-2019-302) project, which is hosted by the University of Glasgow’s COGITO Epistemology Research Centre, and he is grateful to the Leverhulme Trust for supporting this research. The authors would also like to thank Gerry Dunne and two anonymous referees for Educational Philosophy and Theory.

References

  • Anderson, E. (2012). Epistemic justice as a virtue of social institutions. Social Epistemology, 26(2), 163–173. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2011.652211
  • Battaly, H. (2017). Testimonial injustice, epistemic vice, and vice epistemology. In The routledge handbook of epistemic injustice, 223–231. Routledge.
  • Beeby, L. (2011). A critique of hermeneutical injustice. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Hardback), 111(3pt3), 479–486. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9264.2011.00319.x
  • Bondy, P. (2010). Argumentative injustice. Informal Logic, 30(3), 263–278. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v30i3.3034
  • Carter, J. A. (2016). Sosa on knowledge, judgment and guessing. Synthese, 197(12), 1–20.
  • Carter, J. A. (2019). On behalf of a bi-level account of trust. Philosophical Studies, 1–24. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01311-2
  • Carter, J. A. (2020a). “Therapeutic Trust.” Manuscript.
  • Carter, J. A. (2020b). Epistemic perceptualism, skill and the regress problem. Philosophical Studies, 177(5), 1229–1254. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01243-x
  • Carter, J. A. forthcoming. De minimis normativism: A new theory of full aptness. Philosophical Quarterly, 71(1), 16–36.
  • Coady, D. (2017). ‘Epistemic Injustice as Distributive Injustice’.
  • Crerar, C. (2016). Taboo, hermeneutical injustice, and expressively free environments. Episteme, 13(2), 195–207. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2015.35
  • Davis, E. (2016). Typecasts, tokens, and spokespersons: A case for credibility excess as testimonial injustice. Hypatia, 31(3), 485–501. https://doi.org/10.1111/hypa.12251
  • Fernandez, M. A. (Ed.). (2016). Performance epistemology: Foundations and applications. Oxford University Press.
  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford University Press Oxford.
  • Goguen, S. (2016). Stereotype threat, epistemic injustice, and rationality. In B. Michael & S. Jennifer (Eds.), Implicit bias and philosoph (p. 216–237). Oxford University Press.
  • Greco, J. (2003). Knowledge as Credit for True Belief. In D. P. Michael & Z. Linda (Eds.), Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology. Oxford University Press.
  • Greco, J. (2009). Knowledge as success from ability. Philosophical Studies, 142(1), 17–26. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9307-0
  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge University Press.
  • Greco, J. (2012). A different virtue epistemology. Philosophy and phenomenological research, 85(1), 1–26. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2011.00567.x
  • Holton, R. (1994). Deciding to trust, coming to believe. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72(1), 63–76. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048409412345881
  • Kelp, C., Boult, C., Broncano-Berrocal, F., Dimmock, P., Ghijsen, H., & Simion, M. (2020). Hoops and Barns: A new dilemma for sosa. Synthese, 197(12), 5187–5202.
  • Kidd, I. J., Medina, J., & Pohlhaus, G. (2017). The routledge handbook of epistemic injustice. Routledge.
  • Lackey, J. (2008). Learning from words. OUP.
  • Lackey, J. (2020). False confessions and testimonial injustice. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 110(1), 43–68.
  • Langton, R. (2010). Miranda fricker epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Hypatia, 25(2), 459–464. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2010.01098.x
  • Luzzi, F. (2016). Testimonial injustice without credibility deficit. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 5(3), 203–211. https://doi.org/10.1002/tht3.212
  • Maitra, I. (2010). The nature of epistemic injustice. Analytic Philosophy, 51(4), 195–211.
  • McKinnon, R. (2016). Epistemic injustice. Philosophy Compass, 11(8), 437–446. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12336
  • McLeod, C. (2015). Trust. The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. In Z. Edward N. (Ed.), Fall 2015. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entriesrust/.
  • Medina, J. (2011). The relevance of credibility excess in a proportional view of epistemic injustice: Differential epistemic authority and the social imaginary. Social Epistemology, 25(1), 15–35. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2010.534568
  • Medina, J. (2012). Hermeneutical injustice and polyphonic contextualism: Social silences and shared hermeneutical responsibilities. Social Epistemology, 26(2), 201–220. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2011.652214
  • Medina, J. (2013). The epistemology of resistance: Gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and the social imagination. Oxford University Press.
  • Medina, J. (2017). Epistemic injustice and epistemologies of ignorance. The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Race, 247–260. Taylor and Francis.
  • Meehan, D. (2020). Epistemic vices and epistemic nudging: A solution? In A. Guy & B. Amiel (Eds.), Epistemic paternalism. Palgrave-MacMillan.
  • Morton, A. (2012). Bounded thinking: Intellectual virtues for limited agents. OUP.
  • Origgi, G. (2012). Epistemic injustice and epistemic trust. Social Epistemology, 26(2), 221–235. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2011.652213
  • Peet, A. (2017). Epistemic injustice in utterance interpretation. Synthese, 194(9), 3421–3443. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0942-7
  • Pohlhaus, G. Jr. (2014). Discerning the primary epistemic harm in cases of testimonial injustice. Social Epistemology, 28(2), 99–114. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2013.782581
  • Pritchard, D. (2012). Anti-luck virtue epistemology. Journal of Philosophy, 109(3), 247–279.
  • Pritchard, D. (2015). Anti-luck epistemology and the Gettier problem. Philosophical Studies, 172(1), 93–111. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0374-0
  • Proust, J. (2013). The philosophy of metacognition: Mental agency and self-awareness. OUP.
  • Sherman, B. R., & Goguen, S. (2019). Overcoming epistemic injustice: Social and psychological perspectives. Rowman & Littlefield International.
  • Simion, M. (forthcoming). Hermeneutical injustice as basing failure. In C. Joseph Adam & B. Patrick (Eds.), Well founded belief: New essays on the epistemic basing relation. Routledge.
  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge, volume 1. Oxford University Press.
  • Sosa, E. (2010). How competence matters in epistemology. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 465–475. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1520-8583.2010.00200.x
  • Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and Agency. Oxford University Press.
  • Sosa, E. (2017). Epistemology. Princeton University Press.
  • Turri, J. (2011). Manifest failure: The Gettier problem solved. Philosopher’s Imprint, 11(8), 1–11.
  • Turri, J. (2016). Knowledge as achievement, more or less. The present and future of virtue epistemology.
  • Wanderer, J. (2012). Addressing testimonial injustice: Being ignored and being rejected. The Philosophical Quarterly, 62(246), 148–169. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9213.2011.712.x
  • Wanderer, J. (2017). Varieties of testimonial injustice. In The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice (pp. 27–40). Routledge.
  • Zagzebski, L. T. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge University Press.