Publication Cover
Inquiry
An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy
Volume 56, 2013 - Issue 5: Addiction and Agency
715
Views
5
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Original Articles

Addiction: An Emergent Consequence of Elementary Choice Principles

Pages 428-445 | Received 06 Apr 2013, Published online: 25 Jun 2013
 

ABSTRACT

Clinicians, researchers and the informed public have come to view addiction as a brain disease. However, in nature even extreme events often reflect normal processes, for instance the principles of plate tectonics explain earthquakes as well as the gradual changes in the face of the earth. In the same way, excessive drug use is predicted by general principles of choice. One of the implications of this result is that drugs do not turn addicts into compulsive drug users; they retain the capacity to say ‘no’. In support of the logical implications of the choice theory approach to addiction, research reveals that most addicts quit using drugs by about age 30, that most quit without professional help, that the correlates of quitting are the correlates of decision making, and, according to the most recent epidemiological evidence, the probability of quitting remains constant over time and independent of the onset of dependence. This last result implies that, after an initial period of heavy drug use, remission is independent of any further exposure to drugs. In short, there is much empirical support for the claim that addiction emerges as a function of the rules of everyday choice.

Notes

1For example, Mukherjee, Emperor of All Maladies.

2For example, Kalivas and O'Brien, ‘Drug Addiction’; Spanagel and Heilig, ‘Addiction and its Brain Science’.

3Agency and Addiction Conference, University of Oslo, November 10–11, 2011.

4O'Brien and McLellan, ‘Myths’; McLellan et al., ‘Drug Dependence’.

5For example, Anthony and Helzer, ‘Syndromes of Drug Abuse’; Stinson et al., ‘Comorbidity’.

6For example, Ainslie and Monterosso, ‘Hyperbolic Discounting’; Becker and Murphy, ‘Theory of Rational Addiction’.

7Herrnstein and Prelec, ‘Theory of Addiction’.

8American Psychiatric Association, Diagnostic and Statistical Manual.

9For examples, see Heyman, Addiction.

10In both graphs, the curves representing the value of the drug reflect the idea that the costs of drug use increase according to the frequency of use raised to a power of 2.0, whereas the benefits increase linearly as a function of use: V = −AX2 + BX + C, where X is the number of drug choice in the last 10 opportunities. The constants were then adjusted so that the function would approximate 0.0 when 10 of the last 10 decisions were to use the drug.

11Herrnstein et al., ‘Utility Maximization and Melioration’; Vaughan, ‘Melioration, Matching, and Maximization’.

12For example, Davison and McCarthy, Matching Law; Herrnstein, ‘On the Law of Effect’, Matching Law; Williams, ‘Reinforcement, Choice’.

13For example, Heyman and Tanz, ‘How to Teach a Pigeon’; Kudadjie-Gyamfi and Rachlin, ‘Temporal Patterning’.

14Heyman, Addiction.

15Ibid.

16For example, McLellan et al., ‘Drug Dependence’; O'Brien and McLellan, ‘Myths’.

17For example, Goldstein et al., ‘Neurocircuitry of Impaired Insight’; Leshner, ‘Addiction is a Brain Disease’.

18For example, Kalivas, ‘Glutamate Homeostasis Hypothesis’.

19For example, McLellan et al., ‘Drug Dependence’; O'Brien and McLellan, ‘Myths’.

20For example, Quenqua, ‘Rethinking Addiction's Roots’.

21For example, Heyman, ‘Quitting Drugs’.

22For example, Anthony and Helzer, ‘Syndromes of Drug Abuse’; Conway et al., ‘Lifetime Comorbidity’; Kessler et al., ‘Lifetime Prevalence’, ‘Prevalence, Severity, and Comorbidity’; Stinson et al., ‘Comorbidity’; Warner et al., ‘Prevalence and Correlates’.

23For example, Heyman, Addiction, ‘Quitting Drugs’.

24For example, Anthony and Helzer, ‘Syndromes of Drug Abuse’; Stinson et al., ‘Comorbidity’.

25For example, Biernacki, Pathways from Heroin Addiction; Waldorf, ‘Natural Recovery’; Waldorf, Reinarman, and Murphy, Cocaine Changes.

26Robinson et al., ‘Cocaine Self-Administration’.

27Ibid., 264.

28Lenoir et al., ‘Intense Sweetness’.

29For example, Robinson and Berridge, ‘Addiction’; Hyman, Malenka, and Nestler, ‘Neural Mechanisms of Addiction’.

30Lenoir et al., ‘Intense Sweetness’.

31Heyman, ‘Preference for Saccharin’.

32For example, Robinson and Berridge, ‘Addiction’.

33Lopez-Quintero et al., ‘Probability and Predictors’.

34Heyman, ‘Quitting Drugs’; Lopez-Quintero et al., ‘Probability and Predictors’.

35Grant and Dawson, ‘National Epidemiological Survey on Alcohol’.

36Heyman, ‘Quitting Drugs’.

37Carlos Blanco kindly made the data available, and versions of this graph without the fitted equations are in Lopez-Quintero et al., ‘Probability and Predictors’.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 169.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.