430
Views
9
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
CONTENT ARTICLES IN ECONOMICS

Curriculum for the Twenty-First Century: Recent Advances in Economic Theory and Undergraduate Economics

Pages 31-50 | Published online: 06 Jan 2011
 

Abstract

Undergraduate economics lags behind cutting-edge economic theory. The author briefly reviews six related advances that profoundly extend and deepen economic analysis: game-theoretic modeling, collective-action problems, information economics and contracting, social preference theory, conceptualizing rationality, and institutional theory. He offers suggestions for incorporating these into the undergraduate classes at various levels. He argues that game-theoretic representation of collective-action problems offers a unifying framework, on par with supply and demand, for political economy. Blending in the other developments deepens our micro-level understanding of internal and external contract enforcement, with implications on nonclearing markets, power, and distribution. At the macro level, these concepts illuminate the role of institutions in economic development and long-term growth. Undergraduate curricula should incorporate these new approaches.

JEL codes:

The author thanks Janet Seiz and Lee Hansen for encouragement, Mark Montgomery and three anonymous referees for useful comments, and Jelal Younes for editing assistance.

Notes

1. Related discussions appeared in Colander, Holt, and Rosser (2005), Colander (2006), and CitationBecker (2007). I focus on theory; I mention, but do not analyze important new empirical work in experimental and behavioral economics.

2. The transformative implications of game theory are reflected by recent Nobel Prize awards to Nash, Schelling, Maskin, and Myerson, among others.

3. Table 1 and this example closely parallel discussion in chapters 11 and 12 of CitationDixit and Skeath (2004).

4. Large group example: society is better off if shoplifters are apprehended, yet without an external enforcement, honest shoppers face a CAP: who would risk confronting a shoplifter?

5. In table 1 we have a symmetric game of assurance when C > D > H = L and a symmetric game of chicken when H > C and L > D. In symmetric battle, add subscripts for players, CA = DB > DA = CB > H = L. Obviously instructors may wish to adjust notation. See Dixit and Skeath (2004, chap. 4, chap. 12) for an intuitive discussion.

6. Stable equilibria in typical supply/demand models arise from negative feedback.

7. Indeed one could argue that the assumption of perfect information is inconsistent with rational pursuit of self-interest: why rule out potential gains from concealing information?

8. In these models, a principal contracts with an agent to perform costly services, which subsequently the principal can observe only imperfectly.

9. A power law distribution more accurately represents complex phenomenon (CitationMiller and Page 2007).

10. This quotation appeared in Bowles and Gintis (2004, 1430).

11. Bowles (2004, 249–57) discussed P–A models with implications. Colander (2008, 325–30) discussed monitoring and incentive compatibility. See Dixit and Skeath (2004, 277–80) for a managerial incentive model. See CitationFerguson (1994) for a link between efficiency wages and bargaining accessible to postintermediate labor economics. CitationMaskin (2008) discussed mechanism design and eliciting information: implementation theory.

12. A limited exception: direct offspring in intergenerational models.

13. Bowles (2004, 97) treated violations of assumption 3 as a separate departure from traditional models. Bowles (1998) discussed violations of assumption 3 in detail.

14. Other types of social preference: pure altruism or spite—unconditional willingness to sacrifice absolute payoffs to help or harm others (CitationFehr and Fischbacher 2002).

15. CitationFehr and Schmidt (1999) also modeled inequality aversion.

16. Earlier examples of reciprocity appeared in Akerlof (1982), Akerlof and CitationYellen (1990), and Fehr and CitationGächter (1998). Bowles (2004, 111) distinguished between strong reciprocity and weak reciprocity. Weak reciprocity connotes a self-interest motivation for reciprocal behavior, as in tit-for-tat in repeated PD games.

17. Economic approaches to social exchange focus on relations to incentives and scarcity, typically with formal modeling, whereas sociologists focus on relations to social standing. Sociological works include CitationBlau (1964) and CitationMolm (1997). Economic works include Barron and Paulson Gjerde (1997), Fehr and CitationFischbacher (2002), CitationGächter and Fehr (1999), CitationHolländer (1990), and Kandel and CitationLazear (1992).

18. See CitationAkerlof and Yellen (1990), Akerlof and Kranton (2005). CitationBewley (1999) and CitationHowitt (2002) reviewed survey evidence on managerial concern for morale. Ferguson (2005) applied social exchange to implicit bargaining power in segmented labor markets.

19. Related arguments appeared in Fehr, Kirchsteiger, and Riedl (1993), Fehr and Falk (1999), Fehr and Gächter (2002).

20. See Schelling (1978, 91–110). For a review of literature on endogenous preferences, see Bowles (1998).

21. I will not attempt to summarize network economics. Miller and CitationPage (2007) discussed network effects as complex social phenomena. Colander (2006) addressed complexity and UG economics. CitationPage (2007) discussed problem-solving network effects of diverse group membership. For a comprehensive text, see CitationJackson (2008).

22. This is free at http://ccl.northwestern.edu/netlogo/. The site offers tutorials and intuitive examples.

23. CitationDixit and Skeath (2004) used essentially the same definition without the modifier “substantive.” Thus, game payoffs may reflect reciprocity, altruism, or spite in addition to standard material rewards.

24. North (1990, chap. 3) offered a scathing critique of traditional assumptions of rational calculation.

25. CitationSpitzer et al. (2007) offered neuroscientific foundations for social norm enforcement. Since many UGs have some exposure to neuroscience from core classes in science or psychology, it is not unreasonable to introduce neural economics, despite an inability to go into depth.

26. See John Maynard CitationSmith (1989). For an insightful recent text, see CitationGintis (2008). For simulations, see CitationEpstein (2006).

27. For Bowles, strategies (not individuals) are the “personae dramatis” of evolutionary game theory (2004, 60).

28. As in biological evolution, selection need not generate any form of social optimum (North 1990, 20–21).

29. Acemoglu, Johnson, and Robinson (2004) do not explicitly discuss evolutionary game theory, but because payoffs influence future configurations, evolutionary modeling could apply.

30. An intuitive summary of evolutionary game theory appears in Dixit and Skeath (2004, chap. 13).

31. Necessary conditions for Coasian bargaining: (1) relevant property rights must be defined; (2) rights must be transferable; and (3) a small number of involved parties (CitationHall and Lieberman 2008, 473). Example: compared to other CAPs related to externalities or public goods, oligopoly bargaining has a small number of players, definable property rights (limiting output), easy monitoring, and a norm of negotiation over business transactions (how many people pay neighbors to turn down music?). Yet, we often consider oligopoly collusion difficult.

32. Organizations are actors (players), institutions are rules; this distinction is important and often unclear.

33. CitationBasu (2000) discussed types of norms. Ostrom (2000) related norms to social enforcement. See also Akerlof (1982), CitationAkerlof and Yellen (1990), and Fehr and Gächter (2000) for economics of social norms.

34. Fudenberg and Maskin (1986) called this proposition the Folk Theorem; see Gintis (2008, 213–19) for examples.

35. Grief, Milgrom, and Weingast (1994) discussed the role of institutional enforcement mechanisms in advancing medieval trade. CitationGrief (1994) similarly stressed the importance of social organization.

36. “But the fact that growth has been more exceptional than stagnation or decline suggests that ‘efficient’ property rights are unusual in history” (North 1981, 6).

37. Laswell's (1935) definition of politics: “who gets what, when and how,” is instructive: property rights are social mechanisms that partially address these political questions. Definitions are contested.

38. A move designed to alter the expectations of other players in a subsequent game to one's advantage, such as altering an agenda to a subsequent meeting. See Dixit and Skeath (2004, chapter 10).

39. Mountains of lawsuits testify to the contested nature of property right definitions.

40. For endogenous growth, dynamic comparative advantage, and distribution: see Aghion, Caroli, and García-Peñalosa (1999). For development and spatial location theory, see CitationKrugman (1997).

41. With commentary, one could teach this chapter by itself after an intermediate micro treatment of game theory.

42. Chapter 11 of CitationDixit and Skeath (2004) presents repeated PD games.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 130.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.