553
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Article Commentary

Emotion, autonoesis, and the self

ORCID Icon
Pages 716-724 | Received 22 Aug 2022, Accepted 15 Dec 2022, Published online: 26 Dec 2022
 

ABSTRACT

I examine LeDoux’s cognitive account of emotions in The Deep History of Ourselves and raise two questions about it. First, LeDoux argues that emotions are autonoetic conscious experiences grounded in episodic memories. I argue that this overlooks the existential emotions, which represent facts about human conditions in a general rather than an episodic fashion. Second, LeDoux suggests that emotions engage the self-schemas and are concerned with one’s own flourishing. I argue that this overlooks the non-eudaimonistic emotions, such as surprise, wonder, and awe, which respond to the pull of the objects but do not view them through the lens of one’s own scheme of ends.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.

Notes

1. It should be noted that not all emotions are concerned with what is happening to oneself at present. Some emotions are directed at the future, such as hope. Some emotions are about happenings in the past, such as regret. Nevertheless, the opponent could argue that all these emotions involve episodic memories in that they represent particular points in time as being in certain ways.

2. LeDoux (Citation2019) claims that “no other animal matches humans in abstract conceptual thought, hierarchical relational reasoning, and pattern processing” (p. 236). If so, it is unlikely that other animals are capable of having existential emotions.

3. Well-being, flourishing, and eudaimonia are used interchangeably throughout this commentary.

4. This aspect of LeDoux’s account resonates with the eudaimonistic account of emotions in the philosophical literature. According to Nussbaum (Citation2001), a well-known proponent of the eudaimonistic account, emotions require eudaimonistic evaluative content. That is, emotions not only ascribe high value to things, but also do so from the perspective of the agent by referring to her important goals and ends (p. 41).

5. According to Darbor et al. (Citation2016), wonder is “related to trying to understand the world, reflected in greater use of cognitive complexity and tentative words,” such as “think,” “because,” or “perhaps” (p. 1188).

6. For example, the ocean can elicit awe because it is physically vast, whereas a complex scientific theory can elicit awe because it is conceptually vast.

7. A similar point can be found in Keltner and Haidt (Citation2003), who argue that “prototypical awe involves a challenge to or negation of mental structures when they fail to make sense of an experience of something vast” (p. 304).

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 480.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.