504
Views
4
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Kant's Theses on ExistenceFootnote

Pages 559-593 | Published online: 14 Aug 2008
 

Notes

∗This is a developed version of the paper, ‘A Categorical difference in Kant: Reality and Modes of Being’, which I presented at Bilkent University Kant Symposium in April 2005. I would like to thank Stephen Voss, Ilhan Inan and Barry Stocker for their very helpful comments on the earlier drafts of this paper. I would also like to thank the anonymous referee who provided me with valuable feedback in revising the paper.

1Unless otherwise stated, all references to these two works of Kant will be to the following English translations: Immanuel Kant, The One Possible Basis for a Demonstration of the Existence of God=Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund (hereafter The One Possible Basis), English and German, translated by Gordon Treash (Lincoln and London: University of Nebraska Press, 1979); Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (hereafter Critique), translated and edited by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998). As is standard, references to the Critique are to the pages of the first (A) and second (B) edition. Kant also presents an almost full repetition of his account of the refutation and the thesis in the Critique in his ‘Lectures on the Philosophical Doctrine of Religion’ (1783–1784), edited within Religion and Rational Theology, translated and edited by A. W. Wood and G. Di Giovanni (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001).

2Kant briefly repeats his views on existence in some of his other post-Critique lectures as well. See, for example, the ‘Ontology’ sections of Metaphysik Mrongovius (1782–1783) and Metaphysik L2 (1790–1791?) in Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Metaphysics, translated and edited by K. Ameriks and S. Naragon (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997). Hereafter, references to Religion and Rational Theology and Lectures on Metaphysics will be, as provided by the Cambridge edition, to the Academy edition, Kant's gesammelte Schriften, Vols 28 and 29 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1900–). In Lectures on Metaphysics too Kant tends to make his entry into the issue of existence with reference to the existence of God: ‘This concept, although it is simple, is still quite difficult, because we apply it to concepts which are sublime beyond all experience and example. E.g., to the concept of God’ (28: 554).

3At the end of his refutation in the Critique, Kant explicitly states that what he demonstrated to be ‘only so much trouble and labor lost’ is the Cartesian version of the ontological argument. There he also mentions Leibniz's name as another representative of the ontological argument that failed to prove a priori the possibility of God (Critique, A602/B630). We can conclude that although Kant has in mind Descartes's version as the general axis of the argument to assault, he also considers Leibniz's claim to complete the former with a modal modification. On the other hand, nowhere in his whole corpus of works does Kant mention Anselm's original argument. Some writers claim that he knew nothing of the latter. See, for instance, Chapter 10 of Charles Hartshorne, Anselm's Discovery: A Re-Examination of the Ontological Proof for God's Existence (La Salle: Open Court, 1965). For Descartes's argument, Chapter 5 of René Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy in Selected Philosophical Writings, translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988); for an extensive discussion of Leibniz's enduring efforts to develop a modal version of the ontological argument, see also Chapters 4 and 8 of Robert Merrihew Adams, Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist (hereafter Leibniz: DTI) (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). For Anselm's version, see Anselm, Proslogion in The Many-faced Argument, edited by J. H. Hick and A. C. McGill (New York: Macmillan, 1967) 4–6.

4In The One Possible Basis, and also with minor differences in some of his other precritical works such as Nova Dilucidatio (1755) and Inaugural Dissertation (1770), Kant offers an alternative ontological proof that does not rely on the containment of existence as a predicate in the concept of God and its being a real predicate. For the English translations of Nova Dilucidatio and Inaugural Dissertation, see Immanuel Kant, Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770. Briefly, Kant argues that for there to be any possibility, its content or what is thought in it must be previously given by something that actually exists, either in it as a determination of it or through it as a consequence (see The One Possible Basis, 83). Therefore, there must be an absolutely necessary being that grounds not only the existence but even the thought or possibility of things in general. In his categorical denial of the possibility of a theoretical proof of the existence of God, Kant tacitly dismisses his own precritical proof together with all the traditional ones. I think the shift in Kant's understanding of modality in the critical period justifies this categorical denial to some extent (see also n18); but as his own proof's line of inference is radically different from the other traditional proofs that he claims to refute and his objections to the latter do not in the least apply to the former, it is still curious that he never designs a separate refutation for his own proof. For an extensive discussion of what might be a justification for Kant's rejection of his own proof, see Mark Fisher and Eric Watkins, ‘Kant on the Material Ground of Possibility: From The Only Possible Argument to the Critique of Pure Reason’,The Review of Metaphysics, 52 (1998) No. 2: 369–95.

5See Charles Hartshorne, Anselm's Discovery: A Re-Examination of the Ontological Proof for God's Existence and again his ‘Is the Denial of Existence Ever Contradictory’, The Journal of Philosophy, 63 (17 February 1966) No. 4: 85–93; Norman Malcolm, ‘Anselm's Ontological Arguments’, The Philosophical Review, 69 (January 1960) No. 1: 41–62; Alvin Plantinga, ‘Kant's Objection to the Ontological Argument’, The Journal of Philosophy, 63 (October 1996) No. 19: 537–46; Lenn E. Goodman, God of Abraham (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).

6See Critique, A593/B621.

7The refutation of the ontological proof in the Critique is the fourth section of a chapter called ‘The Ideal of Pure Reason’, which is one of the most important parts of the whole Critique and a very difficult one to interpret. In the previous three sections, Kant explains how the idea of God as an ens realissimum, an individual being that contains the sum total of all possible predicates of things, is generated by pure reason as a necessary consequence of one of its natural procedures, and is then speculatively matched with the idea of an absolutely necessary being. The difficulty of interpretation arises from the dubiousness of the mentioned part, which allows different ways of reading, namely as a critique of a natural tendency of pure reason itself, as a critique of traditional speculative theologies in general and as a critique of a particular, i.e. Leibniz's, notion of God. I believe that all three readings can be accepted simultaneously. For reasons of economy, I would like only to point out here that the most significant accomplishment of this chapter, which also includes the refutations of the cosmological and what Kant calls the physico-theological proofs, is reformulating God as a transcendental presupposition necessary for the function of the faculty of understanding; and yet being a mere ideal of pure reason, God is, strictly speaking, not an object of possible experience and His existence cannot be proved whatever theoretical means is used. This is a major step in the whole critical project to secularize the concept of God and to relocate it in the practical domain as a regulative principle, away from the need for any ontological argument for His existence.

8My emphases, Critique, A594/B622.

9 Critique, A595/B623.

10In Kant's language, the broader sense of the term ‘objective reality’ (objekive Realität) refers to the applicability of a concept to an object of intuition in general, either empirical or pure. This sense of the term captures Kant's precritical notion of the real element of possibility which denotes, without an empirical modal commitment, the data or material that is represented through a logically possible concept (see also n18). However, since Kant's intention in using the term here, as will be seen in the next section, is to underline the distinction between the ‘logical possibility of concepts’ that can be tested through mere concepts and the ‘real possibility of things’ that can be tested only with an appeal to the ‘principles of possible experience’, my impression is that in the present context ‘objective reality’ has a somewhat more empirical emphasis and refers to a concept's applicability to possible objects of empirical experience. Heidegger and Hanna prefer to use even stronger language in their definitions; the former identifies objective reality simply with actuality or existence, the latter takes it to be the ‘reference or applicability’ of a representation to ‘actual, real, or existing objects’. See Heidegger, Basic Problems of Phenomenology (hereafter Basic Problems), translated by Albert Hofstadter (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982) 34; and Robert Hanna, Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001) 84. Nevertheless, I believe that the sense of objective reality I suggest above serves better to keep the spirit of the distinction between ‘possibility’ and ‘actuality’ of objects to which Kant refers in the Postulates.

11See Norman Malcolm, ‘Anselm's Ontological Arguments’, 58. For Kant's claim which forms the basis of Malcolm's objection, see Critique A595/B623.

12Malcolm suggests that Kant's real view cannot be that ‘necessity is properly predicated only of propositions (judgments) not of things’. As for his ground of objection, he refers to Kant's discussion of ‘The Postulates of Empirical Thought in General’, where Kant establishes the criterion of necessary existence. See Malcolm's n33, in ‘Anselm's Ontological Arguments’. I will try to show how inaccurate Malcolm's understanding of the postulate of necessity is in the final section.

13James Van Cleve, Problems from Kant, (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999) 192.

15Ibid., A597/B625.

14For Kant, the ens realissimum notion of God and the nominal definition of God as that whose non-being is impossible are generated by two distinct procedures of pure reason, the former being the consequence of pure reason's drive for the complete or thoroughgoing determination of things, the latter being the consequence of the drive to reach the unconditioned in the series of conditions. Kant humourously narrates the story of the speculative match that pure reason makes between these two originally distinct notions: ‘First it convinces itself of the existence of some necessary being. In this it recognizes an unconditioned existence. Now it seeks for the concept of something independent of all conditions, and finds it … in that which contains all reality’ (ibid., A587/B615). However, although he thinks that the notion of an absolutely necessary being is fundamentally confused, he holds the view that the notion of a most real being, as will be seen, is logically possible.

16 Critique, A596/B624.

17Kant, in the present context, does not explicitly make a distinction between positive and negative predicates. He rather seems to take ‘predicates’ as positive attributes that make up the real content of things: ‘Logical negation … is never properly attached to a concept, but rather only to its relation to another concept in a judgment, and therefore it is far from sufficient to designate a concept in regard to its content’ (ibid., A574/B602). In the case of the idea of ens realissimum, as it contains all reality, it lacks no real content and thus must have only ‘positive’ predicates. That the ens realissimum has the sum total only of positive predicates can be further confirmed by resorting to Leibniz, whose notion of God, I believe, Kant considers here. However, the question about the ens realissimum is whether containing only positive predicates entails freedom from internal contradiction and thus ensures logical possibility, because there are positive predicates that are not logically opposite to each other, and yet cannot be contained in the same subject. For Kant's solution to this problem that preoccupied Leibniz for a long time, see n43. For the moment, as the logical criterion of possibility is only a formal one and abstracts from all content, it is still not wrong to conclude that the concept of a being that contains only positive predicates is logically possible.

18This distinction is a good example of how Kant amended his precritical understanding of modality in the Critique. In The One Possible Basis, Kant makes an apparently similar distinction in the concept of possibility, between what he calls the formal or logical element and the real element. The formal element of possibility, in conformity with the logical possibility of concepts, refers to the Leibnizian notion of possibility that is constituted by freedom from contradiction alone. On the other hand, the real element of possibility, which Kant borrowed from Baumgarten, refers to the givenness of the material or data of possibility through which what is to be possible is thought or represented. However, this wide field of possibility which applies to all that is representable, given in whatever way, is narrowed in the Critique, by imposing not only conceptual but also sensible conditions, i.e. space and time, on the givenness and consequently on the real possibility of things. (As possibility itself is one of the modal categories, this further, critical constraint on the notion of possibility goes along with the requirement that categories must be applicable to sensible intuition to provide real cognition of things.) As discussed in the final section of this essay, what is possible is thus identified with a possible object of experience. This is how the precritical notion of the real element of possibility is developed into the notion of real possibility in Kant's critical programme of modality. For the precritical distinction, see The One Possible Basis, 67. For Kant's terminological connection with Baumgarten, see also Heidegger, Basic Problems, 34–5, and the translator's introduction to The One Possible Basis, 19–21; and for Kant's specific indebtedness to Baumgarten for the form of the ontological argument that Kant claims to refute, see Charles Hartshorne, Anselm's Discovery: A Re-Examination of the Ontological Proof for God's Existence, Part Two, Chapter 10.

19 Critique, A597/B625. This surely is not a contradiction in the strict, logical sense of the term. What Kant means, I think, is that while through the mere concept of a thing what could only be tested is the concept's logical possibility which would not even suffice to prove the real possibility of the thing itself, introducing existence as a predicate into the concept of a thing and thereby making an existential commitment for the thing in question would be falling into a fundamental confusion concerning the use of modal concepts.

20See Anselm, Proslogion (Chs 2–4) in The Many-faced Argument, 4–6.

21‘[I] am not free to think of God without existence (that is, a supremely perfect being without a supreme perfection) …' (Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy in Selected Philosophical Writings, 107).

22Heidegger emphasizes the radical character of Kant's objection: ‘Kant's thesis … does not assert merely that existence cannot belong to the concept of the most perfect being … It goes further. It says, fundamentally, that something like existence does not belong to the determinateness of a concept at all’ (Heidegger, Basic Problems, 32).

23The problem of the possibility of an existence producing machine is first pointed out by Gaunilo, the immediate critic of Anselm's argument. He argues that if the minor premise of Anselm's argument that ‘that which exists is more excellent than that which stands in relation to my understanding only’ is accepted, then the mere idea of the most excellent ‘lost island’, by virtue of its perfection, would suffice to prove that it necessarily exists. See Gaunilo and Anselm, ‘Criticism and Reply’ in The Many-faced Argument, 22–3. There are various modern objections to Gaunilo's argument on the ground that the idea of a greatest possible island is neither analogous to the concept of God, nor a consistent idea for there is no end to the greatness of an island. See, for instance, Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom and Evil (New York: Harper & Row, 1977) 91. However, as the purest form of the syllogism in the minor premise of the ontological argument exhibits, the problem here is the very introduction of existence into the mere concept of something, not the way in which or, as Kant would say, the disguise under which this introduction is conducted. Thus, even if he may be said to fail to give a convincing example, Gaunilo's anticipation of Kant's objection is still impressive.

24 Critique, A597/B625.

25Ibid., A7/B11.

26Ibid., A598/B626.

27Although it has never been as popular as his thesis that existence is not a real predicate, Kant's claim to the categorical syntheticity of all existential propositions has received serious criticisms from the literature on the refutation. One specific criticism that has been frequently repeated by not only the proponents but also the opponents of the ontological argument is that the latter thesis is not compatible with the former one. For only three of the typical examples of this sort of allegation, see Jerome Schaffer, ‘Existence, Predication, and the Ontological Argument’, Mind, New Series, 71 (1962) No. 283: 309:

Kant defines [real predicate] as something ‘which is added to the concept of the subject and enlarges it’. This is a most unfortunate definition for Kant to use, however, since it leads to contradiction with another important doctrine of his, that existential propositions are synthetic.

Nicholas Everitt, The Non-Existence Of God (London and NewYork: Routledge, 2004) 52:

This appears to commit him to saying that ‘exists’ does enlarge the subject concept, and hence that ‘exists’ passes both tests for being a real predicate… Indeed, it seems that Kant's own words commit him to denying the thesis as well as asserting it;

and Lenn E. Goodman, God of Abraham, 67: ‘His claim that all existential propositions are synthetic is inconsistent with his thesis that “exists” is not a real predicate’. In the second part, I will discuss how this way of identifying the syntheticity of propositions with the predicate's enlarging of the subject or its being a real predicate fails to capture the true senses of Kant's notions of syntheticity and existence.

28 Critique, A598/B626. Norman Kemp-Smith translates the original term ‘Bestimmung’ as ‘determining predicate’; compare the same quotation in Immanuel Kant, Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Norman Kemp-Smith (New York: Palgrave, 1929). The idea of determination being a real predicate that adds to the subject concept comes from pure reason's principle of thoroughgoing or complete determination of things: ‘Every thing … as to its possibility … stands under the principle … according to which, among all possible predicates of things, in so far as they are compared with their opposites, one must always apply to it; (Critique, A572/B600). The principle is in fact a manifestation of what is required to know things completely with their determinate contents. To know something completely, one has to know the sum total of all possible predicates (the idea which brings about the concept of ens realissimum, of the individual being that is determined by this idea alone) and determine the thing through them, either affirmatively or negatively (see ibid., A573/B60). Real or determining predicates are therefore ones that contribute to this ideal process of thoroughgoing determination.

31Henry E. Allison, Kant's Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1983) 71; my emphasis. In some of his critical works Kant prefers to call real predicates synthetic predicates, and thereby applies the analytic/synthetic distinction to predicates themselves in a way that allows Allison's interpretation. See, for example, Lectures on Metaphysics, 28: 552: ‘We call determinations not analytic predicates [praedicata analytica] but rather synthetic predicates [praedicata synthetica]'. However, as will be discussed in the rest of this essay, given the exceptional status of modal propositions, the syntheticity of propositions does not warrant qualifying their predicates as real, determining or synthetic predicates. Kant puts this clearly: ‘… we have introduced the categories: possibility, actuality, and necessity, and then we deemed that they are not at all determinations of a thing, or synthetic predicates’ (ibid., 29: 822).

29Sebastian Gardner, Kant and the Critique of Pure Reason (London: Routledge, 1999) 239.

30See Heidegger, Basic Problems, 33–4.

32 Critique, A599/B627.

33Compare the mentioned quotation in Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Werkausgabe Band IV), (Frankfurt am Main: Shurkamp, 1996): ‘Sein ist offenbar kein reales Prädikat …’.

34 The One Possible Basis, 57; my emphasis. Compare ibid., 56: ‘Das Dasein ist gar kein Prädikat oder Determination von irgend einem Dinge’. This shortcut formulation of Kant might have been thought as the textual source of the widely exemplified misconception of his thesis in the literature, i.e. that it is not a predicate at all; but then in the same text, Kant goes on to explain the sense in which existence may be used as a predicate.

35See n28.

36Heidegger grounds his interpretation of Kant's thesis on the importance of this sense of ‘reality’, which, he claims, is adopted by Kant from Scholastic terminology:

When Kant talks about the omnitudo realitatis, the totality of all realities, he means not the whole of all beings actually extant but, just the reverse, the whole of all possible thing-determinations, the whole of all thing-contents or real-contents, essences, possible things. Accordingly, realitas is synonymous with Leibniz's term possibilitas, possibility. Realities are the what-contents of possible things in general without regard to whether or not they are actual, or ‘real’ in our modern sense;

(Heidegger, Basic Problems, 34)
For a similar articulation of the distinction between reality and existence in Kant's language, see also Wolfgang Schwarz, ‘Kant's Categories of Reality and Existence’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 48 (December 1987) No. 2: 343–6. As Heidegger finds it synonymous with the Leibnizian notion of possibility, I think this sense of reality is better captured by Kant's precritical notion of ‘real element of possibility’ that I alluded to in n18. Just like the real element of possibility, it designates a neutral notion of possibility. It is free of any modal reference in the critical sense; that is, it does not involve a reference to the agreement of the object with the conditions of experience in general, but it refers solely to the data or content that is represented by the concept. Traces of this precritical neutral notion of possibility are still present in the Critique, and at times it becomes a really taxing business to differentiate the sense in which Kant uses the term ‘possibility’.

37Richard Campbell, in his ‘Real Predicates and “Exists”‘, suggests a misleading reading of Kant's discourse of real or determining predicates. Campbell's idea is that ‘although the notion of a determining predicate is to be understood relative to a given judgment’, the notion of a real predicate is not. He obviously assumes a distinction between the meanings of the two terms, which, I believe, Kant uses interchangeably to refer to the same notion. Without giving a satisfactory account of the distinction he has in mind, he bases his own, revised definition of a real predicate upon this alleged distinction: ‘… a real predicate is one which is apt to serve as a determining predicate’, or again in the footnote to the former definition, ‘one which could add a determination in some judgment’ (96). I have the impression that Campbell takes ‘real predicate’ as a broader notion to mean a concept that has a capacity to function as a determining predicate, whether or not it actually does so. That is probably why he thinks the notion of a real predicate, in contradistinction with that of a determining predicate, is not relative to a propositional context. However, besides introducing an unnecessary and unexplained distinction between real and determining predicates, Campbell understands Kant's negative thesis concerning existence as a positive definition of a real predicate, and thus reads the ‘could’ in ‘Being is not … a concept of something that could add to the concept of a thing’ as a capacity that every real predicate, in isolation from any propositional context, must have. I suggest, however, that the ‘could’ in question refers to the context-independent incapacity of ‘being’ or ‘existence’ to add to the concept of a thing as a predicate, and thus classifies existence as a non-real predicate, tout court. On the other hand, a real or determining predicate is one which actually adds (a further determination) to the concept of a thing in a given proposition. What Campbell defines as a concept that could or is apt to add a determination to the concept of a thing, without any mention of a propositional context, may correspond in my account only to what I classified above as a potentially real or determining predicate. See Richard Campbell, ‘Real Predicates and ‘Exists’, Mind, New Series, 83 (January 1974) No. 329: 95–9.

38See Heidegger, Basic Problems, 29–34.

39Heidegger devotes the entire second chapter of his Basic Problems to the history of this assumption.

40This distinction can be traced back to Aristotle and his early medieval commentators such as Aquinas. At many places in his Metaphysics, Aristotle distinguishes the categories as the figures of predication, or more precisely, as the attributes that constitute the essence of an individual thing, from the other ways in which a thing is said to be, i.e. being accidentally, being as truth, being potentially or actually. See especially, Aristotle, Metaphysics in The Complete Works of Aristotle, edited by Jonathan Barnes. (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1984) 1026a 33ff. Aquinas, in his On Being and Essence, clarifies that the term ‘essence’ applies only to the first sense of being that is divided into ten categories, and points out that as it is what is signified by the definition of what the thing is, essence is also called by the name ‘whatness;’ see St Thomas Aquinas, Selected Writings, translated and edited by Ralph McInerny (London: Penguin Books, 1998) 31. In his Lectures on Metaphysics, Kant himself repeatedly draws this categorical distinction between essentia and existentia, or what and modes of being and calls modes ‘extraessential’ properties that do not belong to the essence of a thing; see, for example, ibid., 28: 553.

41 Critique, A80, B106.

42‘[T]ranscendental affirmation … is called reality (thinghood)’ (ibid., A574/B602).

43Kant makes a warning about the original function of the ens realissimum in the derivation of the particular possibilities of things:

The derivation of all other possibility from this original being … cannot be regarded as a limitation of its highest reality and as a division, as it were of it; for then the original being would be regarded as a mere aggregate of derivative beings … Rather, the highest reality would ground the possibility of all things as a ground and not as a sum total; the manifoldness of the former rests not on the limitation of the original being itself, but on its complete consequences.

(ibid., A579/B607)
Kant is aware that his previous discourse of ‘possessing/containing all reality’ may lead the reader to a Spinozistic notion of God, which he thinks, as containing all realities within itself, suffers from real internal conflicts. Kant addresses this problem of real conflicts in the Amphiboly, where he directly criticizes Leibniz:

the principle that realities (as mere affirmations) never logically oppose each other … signifies nothing at all either in regard to nature nor overall in regard to anything in itself (of this we have no concept). For real opposition always obtains … i.e., where one reality, if combined in one subject with another, cancels out the effect of the latter

(ibid., A273/B329)
This problem, which Kant has had in mind even in the precritical period, was what required a revision in the Leibnizian–Wolffian notion of possibility, whose only criterion is freedom from logical contradiction; hence the Baumgartenian distinction between the logical and real element of possibility that I explained in n18. However, Kant's ground notion of God, together with the notion of particular possibilities (or realities) as its consequences, avoids such real oppositions. In The One Possible Basis, Kant proposes a similar solution by dividing possibilities into two classes with respect to their relation with God, namely the ones that belong to its own determinations and the ones that belong to its consequences. See, ibid., 83–5. Here, it is also useful to keep in mind the distinction between the idea of the sum total (of all reality) and the ideal of the most real being; for what is limited in deriving particular possibilities is the former but strictly not the latter.

44The quality of judgements is not in fact the only function that has to do with the content of a judgement. See, for example, Critique, B100, where Kant implies that except for the modality of judgements, all other three functions (quality, quantity and relation) constitute the content of a judgement. However, our present inquiry is about the determination of particular thing-contents, or of particular subjects in judgements, and as will be seen, about the use of the ‘is’ of predication in such determination. In other words, we are dealing with the kinds of judgement that pertain to the ‘reality’ of things. Therefore, the direct focus of our account will be qualitative judgements that are particular with respect to their function of quantity and categorical with respect to their function of relation.

45Infinite judgements and the corresponding category of limitation have a special place in the qualitative relation between the subject and the predicate. As they contain a peculiar sort of affirmation made by means of a merely negative predicate, infinite judgements do not immediately determine the object of the subject, but placing the subject in a separated class of beings within the infinite domain of all possible beings, they contribute, in a limiting way, to the content of our cognition in general. This limiting function of infinite judgements is also one of the marks that distinguishes Kant's transcendental logic from what he calls ‘general logic’; see, for example, Critique, A72–3 and A574/B602.

46Heidegger, Basic Problems, 36.

47Kant explains the indifference of modal categories to the ‘reality’ or determination of things more clearly in Lectures on Metaphysics:

Everything that exists is, to be sure, thoroughly determined … Existence, however, is not a concept of thoroughgoing determination … Existence thus gives no further predicate to the thing … Existence is not a separate reality, although everything that exists must have a reality. Existence, possibility, actuality, and necessity are special kinds of categories which do not at all contain predicates of things, but rather only modes;

(ibid., 28: 554)

48 Lectures on Metaphysics, 28: 552.

49Van Cleve makes exactly the same point: ‘Note that “enlarge” may be a misleading term, insofar as enlarging a concept typically results in narrowing its extension.’ See Problems From Kant, 188.

50In his Lectures on Metaphysics, Kant applies the logical/real duality to the concept of essence.

A logical essence [he says] is the first inner ground of all logical predicates of a thing; a real essence is the first inner ground of all determinations of an essence … Logical essence is found through principles of analysis: but real essence through principles of synthesis;

(ibid., 28: 553)
Regarding the problem of further determination, we can thus conclude that the predicates that we reach through the analysis of a concept are merely logical predicates and the ones that further determine this complex of logical predicates (logical essence) through synthesis are real predicates. However, there is still the exception of modes which Kant calls ‘extraessential’ properties. Although they can be contained neither in the logical essence (we cannot reach the mode of a subject through its analysis) nor in the real essence of a thing, they can function as logical predicates in modal propositions, because as long as it occupies the predicate position ‘anything one likes can serve as a logical predicate’.

51 Critique, A599/B627.

53 The One Possible Basis, 59.

52 The One Possible Basis, 59. The literal translation of the German word ‘Setzung’ is ‘setting’; but, as Heidegger says, it is not more helpful than ‘positing’: ‘[O]ur German word Setzung is just as ambiguous as the Latin positio. The latter can mean: (1) Setting, placing, laying as action. (2) Something set, the theme. (3) Setness, site, constitution' (Martin Heidegger, ‘Kant's Thesis about Being’ in Pathmarks, 343). All these senses amount to the idea that to be is to be set in (or to have) a position.

54See n44.

55 Critique, A599/B627.

57 The One Possible Basis, 61. This suggestion of Kant, together with his general attitude concerning the ‘is’ of predication, that we do not commit ourselves to an ontological position on the existence or even on the objective reality of the subject by ascribing a predicate to it, may invite some semantic objections. In modern logical theory, whether the truth of positive propositions requires or implies the existence of the subject, or whether propositions about non-existent entities have a truth-value at all are controversial questions. But it will not be wrong to say that it is a fairly common interpretation that predicates can be ascribed with truth only to existing things, or in other words, ‘the being that is expressed by the copula’ is not as indifferent to the existence of the subject as Kant suggests. In relation to the same point, Van Cleve brings up a quite reasonable doubt that I myself would share: whether Kant is here committing himself to a Meinongian ontology, or to the so-called Independence Principle. However, he distinguishes Kant from Meinong by referring to the possibility of reconstructing Kant's qualitative judgements as conditionals:

Not necessarily, for his observation [that ‘God is omnipotent’ is true even if God does not exist] can be accommodated by construing the predication as a conditional: if any being is God, that being is omnipotent. That in turn can be construed as asserting a link between two concepts rather than a link between a Meinongian object and a predicate.

(See Van Cleve, Problems From Kant, 304)
For a relevant discussion, see also Adams, Leibniz:DTI, 159–60.

58 Critique, A599/B627.

56See n18.

59Ibid., A599/B627. This dictum (and the following example of hundred dollars), Kant seems to intend as a direct reply to Leibniz who repeatedly states the opposite of what Kant says about the relation between existence and degrees of reality and sees existence as the complement of possibility: It is clear … that Existence is a perfection, or increases reality; that is, when existing A is conceived, more reality is conceived than when possible A is conceived'; ‘[Y]et if we consider more accurately, [we shall see] that we conceive something more when we think that a thing A exists, than when we think it is possible;' respectively quoted in Adams, Leibniz: DTI, 120, 165.

60 Critique, A599/B627.

62Alvin Plantinga, ‘Kant's Objection to the Ontological Argument’, 539–40.

61See ibid., A573/B601.

63S. Morris Engel, ‘Kant's ‘Refutation’ of the Ontological Argument’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 24 (September 1963) No. 1: 30.

64For Wolfgang Schwarz's apt reply to Engel in relation to this point, see Wolfgang Schwarz, ‘Professor Engel on Kant’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 25 (March 1965) No. 3: 409.

65 Critique, A601/B628

66Ibid., A601/B628.

67I believe I have already said enough of why Kant thinks that his thesis concerning existence is a basic ground of attack that might suffice to refute the ontological argument as he reconstructs it. I should add here, however, that the force of the thesis to refute the ontological argument is not universally accepted, even among those who accept the thesis itself. Van Cleve, for instance, claims that existence is not a real predicate, even if it is assumed as true, is irrelevant or at least harmless to Descartes's argument. See his Problems from Kant, 189. A much more radical claim is one made by Nakhnikian and Salmon: ‘The treatment of “exists” as a real predicate does not render the ontological argument valid. If anything, it helps to clarify the invalidity of the argument’. See George Nakhnikian, Wesley C. Salmon, ‘“Exists” as a Predicate’, The Philosophical Review, 66 (October 1957) No. 4: 542. As I declared at the beginning, my concern in this paper is not to discuss and take a position on the validity or soundness either of the ontological argument, or of Kant's alleged refutation of it, but to understand Kant's notion of existence by the help of his thesis as presented in the context of the refutation. In relation to these objections, I should be content with just stating my basic approach to them. One may not be convinced by Kant's reconstruction of the ontological argument; and one may have reasons for rejecting the thesis as well; but challenging that the latter is relevant to the former in the specific way Kant suggests can only be an indication of an improper understanding of either one or the other or both.

68Maybe not in the Critique explicitly, but in the title of the second section of the first chapter of The One Possible Basis Kant uses the term ‘absolute position’: ‘Das Dasein ist die absolute Position eines Dinges’.

69Immanuel Kant, Werke, Akademieausgabe, Vol. 18, No. 6276, quoted in Heidegger, ‘Kant's Thesis about Being’, Pathmarks, edited by William McNeill (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998) 344.

70Immanuel Kant, Religion and Rational Theology, 28: 1028. See also Critique, A599/B627.

71Robert Hanna, Kant and The Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, 192–3.

72 Critique, A601/629.

73Ibid., B266.

74Ibid., A225.

75Ibid., A226.

76From here, Heidegger reaches, rather promptly, the conclusion that ‘the specific character of absolute position, as Kant defines it, reveals itself as perception;’ Heidegger, Basic Problems, 46. This conclusion is valid but somehow conceals the fundamental difference between the foundations of the two positive theses concerning existence that I mentioned above. It is always useful to keep in mind that Kant's thesis of absolute positing is essentially about what it means to say in a proposition that a thing exists. On the other hand, the postulate of actuality is about the empirical conditions of actuality, in other words, it defines the criteria under which a subject can be posited absolutely. Therefore, the postulate is a supplementary thesis about what exists rather than what existence is.

78 Critique, B 280.

77See Norman Malcolm, ‘Anselm's Ontological Arguments’, n 33.

79For Kant's own reformulation of modalities in terms of positing, see Lectures on Metaphysics, 29: 822 and 28: 554–5.

80Whether Kant's refutation works in itself as an argument in isolation from the critical framework is a question that is worth to ask here. At the final analysis, the proponent of the ontological proof may always reject to endorse Kant's critical philosophy, if the refutation is presented as essentially dependent on it. However, as I indicated at the beginning, my concern in this paper has not been to discuss the validity of neither the proof nor the alleged refutation, but to investigate Kant's notion of existence (and modality in general) as presented in the refutation and to exhibit its integrity with his critical account of modality as a whole.

81Allen W. Wood, ‘Kant's Critique of the Three Theistic Proofs [partial]’ (from Kant's Rational Theology) in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Critical Essays, edited by P. Kitcher, 273–4.

82See Critique, A234:

The principles of modality are not, however, objective-synthetic, since the predicates of possibility, actuality, and necessity do not in the least augment the concept of which they are asserted in such a way as to add something to the representation of the object. But since they are nevertheless always synthetic, they are so subjectively only, i.e., they add to the concept of a thing (the real), about which they do not otherwise say anything, the cognitive power whence it arises and has its seat, so that, if it is merely connected in the understanding with the formal conditions of experience, its object is called possible; if it is in connection with perception (sensation, as the matter of the senses), and through this determined by means of the understanding, then the object is actual; and if it is determined through the connection of perceptions in accordance with concepts, then the object is called necessary.

This distinction, I believe, may shed further light not only on the peculiar syntheticity of modal propositions but also on syntheticity in general. However, in this paper I should be content with leaving the interpretation of this striking distinction as an open question for another study.

83This idea of Kant's that by asserting that a thing exists, we do not say something about the thing but its concept, when taken together with his dictum that existence is not a real predicate, anticipates Frege's celebrated view that existence is a property not of objects but only of concepts, and that it is itself a second-level concept. See, for instance, Frege's ‘On Concept and Object’, in Translations From the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, edited by Peter Geach and Max Black (Oxford: Blackwell, 1960).

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 286.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.