2,526
Views
18
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

The normativity of possession. Rethinking land relations in early-modern Spanish America, ca. 1500–1800

Introduction

This article advocates a critical reading of the historiography of land rights in early-modern Spanish America. The main argument is that since the 1940s’ tradition of the derecho indiano, rights to land have been understood fundamentally under the anachronistic idea of private property. This has become increasingly problematic in more recent historiography, which focuses on the intersection of indigenous and Spanish land relations, presented as a conflict between individual and collective notions of property. While this emphasis on the ‘cultural’ differences of ownership and tenure representations is certainly important, more often than not it rests on the assumption that historians know much more about the European worldview than the indigenous worldview. And though this may be true of the archive available to the historian,Footnote1 which reveals the vision of the Spanish conquerors more than that of the indigenous populations of America, the dichotomous representation of land relations as a difference between European and indigenous-American cultures has constructed a blind spot for historical research: the focus on the otherness of indigenous modes of land tenure and use has led historians to neglect the otherness of the normative order that regulated land relations within the framework of the European ius commune. From a twenty-first-century perspective, both indigenous and Spanish representations of land tenure are incommensurable with our contemporary notions of land, property, and rights.

The anachronistic reading of the law of the early modern period began in the nineteenth century with the beginning of the theoretical and institutional separation of the public from the private (Blaufarb Citation2016). The radical transformation in legal thought that began with the rise of private law was reflected, unlike in any other legal category, in the institution of possession. Within the emerging legalist framework, jurists struggled to make sense of possession as the actual holding of a thing: if only the owner had the right to possess a thing, how could mere possession be a basis for rights? This question addressed the difficulty of explaining why the law protected possession regardless of whether the possessor was the owner or not: ‘if the possessor who is not the owner is acting without right, the law is protecting the will to do something wrongful’ (Gordley and Mattei Citation1996, 298). As James Gordley and Ugo Mattei argue, nineteenth-century legal scholars were unable to provide a satisfactory answer to the tensions posed by the contradiction generated by the legal protection of possession because the problem itself was constructed on an inadequate premise:

Once continental jurists had defined the owner as a person with the right to possession, it seemed to them that they had to define the mere possessor as a person without this right. Once they had done so they entered a theoretical box canyon from which they never emerged. (Gordley and Mattei Citation1996, 293)

This manner of addressing the issues of ownership and possession not only had consequences for legal doctrine, but also permeated much of the historical research on land relations in Spanish America.Footnote2 While the derecho indiano tradition of legal historical research created an image of legislatively guided distribution of land among Spaniards and the recognition of existing ‘property rights’ for indigenous populations, more recent social historical research based on judicial records presents a more dynamic picture. Instead of the allocation of land rights by virtue of a central policy, land was at the center of conflictive relations, occupation, and dispossession, thus creating an overall image of more fluid relations of ownership. However, despite the methodological difference between both traditions, they share the assumption that law should have protected property rights and that the judicial protection of possession—considered as a merely factual, mostly ‘illegal,’ form of tenure—was the consequence of the imperfect functioning of law.

This article argues that, in order to better interpret judicial sources on land relations in Spanish America, it is essential to move away from the category of ‘property’ and move toward an understanding of the peculiar normative order in which the legal protection of possession made sense. The following sections will present this argument in three steps. First, the literature on land rights produced by the tradition of the derecho indiano, which has been one of the central sources for understanding land relations in the historiography of Spanish America, will be discussed. While producing some of the seminal studies concerned with how Spain governed in the Americas, its characterization of the legal model of land tenure has been one of the main means of misrepresentation regarding how Europeans viewed property more generally. Second, by acknowledging the more recent legal-historical research on the European ius commune and its jurisdictional culture, the ways in which this manner of representing law could help better understand the logic of judicial sources for historical research will be expanded on. Third, some of the more recent studies into land tenure will be revisited in order to illustrate that different manners of understanding the functioning of law can lead to widely diverging historical interpretations.

Land rights in the tradition of the derecho indiano

The scholarly tradition of the derecho indiano has arguably played the leading role in the reconstruction of the legal history of Spanish America. Although it is supposed to refer to the legal situation in colonial Spanish America, the term has suffered broad reformulations since Ricardo Levene (Citation1916) first coined it in the early twentieth century. Initially conceived as a sociology of the law in the Indies, seen by Levene as an outcome of the ‘social life’ of the peoples governed by the Spanish Crown in the sixteenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth centuries, it later took on a more narrow focus on the ‘laws’ that governed Spanish rule in the Americas. While this shift can already be seen in the 1940s in the work of José María de Ots Capdequí, it was Alfonso García Gallo (Citation1970) who, in the 1950s, reduced the derecho indiano to a legislative outcome of the action of the Spanish state.Footnote3 Despite recent attempts by Victor Tau Anzoátegui (Citation1982, Citation1992) to move away from this stricter definition, the emphasis on the legislative action of the state has had an enduring influence in shaping the representations of land relations in Spanish America. As a detailed discussion of the contributions of the derecho indiano for the (legal) historiography of Spanish America would exceed the scope of this article, in this section, the focus lies less on the historical research carried out by the historians of the derecho indiano and more on their representation of land relations in Spanish America.

The discussion of the legal foundations of the Spanish American land regime has particularly been shaped by José María Ots Capdequí, Mario Góngora, and José María Mariluz Urquijo. All begin with the assumption that Roman law played an important role in configuring land relations in Spanish America, specifically focusing on the idea of absolute, private property rights. While Ots Capdequí uses the distinction of public and private law to present the historical development of land relations as a permanent conflict between the interests of the Crown and of private landholders, Mariluz Urquijo follows Góngora in suggesting that the Spanish Crown used the public/private distinction to recognize the preexistence of indigenous property rights. Although different, these interpretations suggest that the derecho indiano theoretically distinguished two quite different property regimes: one in which the state created land rights and one in which private property existed independently from state action.

Ots Capdequí traces the introduction of the distinction between public and private law to the reception of the Justinian Code in Europe in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries and credits its influence to the rise of the monarchic state. According to him, this normative shift transformed the definition of the royal land holdings, the realengo, rendering them a regalía, thus no longer considered part of the personal holdings of the king, but part of the ‘assets of the Crown, the Monarchy, the State’ (Ots Capdequí Citation1946, 21; italics in original). The reception of Roman law, thus, led to the rise of the absolutist monarchy in which public powers were concentrated in the person of the king, in his role as head of state, and no longer in the patrimonial sense characteristic of the late Middle Ages. Ots Capdequí follows Sólorzano’s Política Indiana to argue that the regalía was the fundamental institution that shaped land rights in Spanish America—‘land was a regalía, and thus all possible rights to particular domain to land had to originally derive from grace, from a merced real’ (Ots Capdequí Citation1946, 41; italics in original). The distribution of rights to land was therefore subordinated to the public interests of the Crown, thus making most mercedes conditional to effective occupation, residence, and tillage. The legal doctrine Ots Capdequí (Citation1946, 77–78; Citation1959, 76–77) identifies as prevailing in the Indies was one of private ownership of land tied to the exercise of a ‘social function,’ thus making property rights conditional to the public interests of the Spanish ‘state.’Footnote4

This doctrine is seen by Ots Capdequí as part of the specific norms of the derecho indiano, what he calls ‘el derecho propiamente indiano,’ which, according to the author, did not recognize the influence of the Roman concepts of absolute, intangible property present, in Spanish law. The tension between Spanish laws—as influenced by Roman law—and the derecho propiamente indiano—centered on the primacy of the monarchic state—set the stage for the evolution of land relations in Spanish America. Thus, the problem of land tenure in Spanish America was the result of the coexistence of two ‘legal systems’—the Spanish and the indiano—whereby the laws designed by the Crown for the Indies were not applied by the magistrates, who instead favored ‘the introduction of Justinian law and impeded the reduction of the powers of ownership (facultades dominicales) over the land, whether the land possessed was abundant or little, whether it was cultivated or uncultivated’ (Ots Capdequí Citation1946, 78). In this sense, the laws of the state, designed to protect and enhance the common good, were undermined by the convictions and decisions of magistrates who, with a bias towards learned law, tended to favor the Roman conceptions of private ownership.

While Ots Capdequí begins with the institution of the regalía, Mario Góngora’s view of the land problem is shaped by the importance he places on the institution of the encomienda in the early stages of the Spanish conquest. Land, Góngora (Citation1951, 149) correctly notes, had very little value if it did not have a stable workforce. Accordingly, the occupation of land in Spanish America began with the occupation of lands by the encomendero in proximity to the pueblos where his encomienda had been granted, giving him access to fertile lands and labor. However, since the institution of the encomienda gave a right to usufruct from the labor of the indigenous community and did not grant the encomendero a right over the land, this institution was an instrument of territorial colonization that did not generate land rights (Borde and Góngora Citation1956, 29). This was convincingly argued by Silvio Zavala (Citation1940, 25), who showed that the encomienda did not generate rights to the land for the encomendero, and that his access to land had to occur through other institutions, such as a merced or through purchase. The importance of the encomienda for Góngora was connected to the question it raised regarding the legal condition of the land occupied by the pueblo: if the indigenous community owns the land, under what title is it owned? Góngora answers this question by drawing on the Roman law distinction between public and private law, arguing that while all Spanish private ownership had to be obtained through a merced, the institution of the encomienda revealed that the Crown recognized indigenous property as preexistent and, therefore, intangible; ‘The constitution of Spanish territorial property, thus, derives first and foremost from mercedes from the state, while that of the Indians subsisted, as preexistent and intangible to royal law, due to the Roman difference of public and private law’ (Góngora Citation1951, 150).

Finally, José María Mariluz Urquijo expanded on the principles established by Ots Capdequí and Góngora by certifying the public/private distinction as a well-established ‘fact’ of the juridical reality of Spanish America. The state, he argued, was the only owner of lands in America, but this ownership was only considered eminent domain or sovereignty and not property in terms of private law. Proof of this, argued Mariluz Urquijo (Citation1968, 22), was that the state ‘respects the preexistent property of the Indians.’ This sleight of hand not only neatly reconciled both arguments discussed above, but it also went further by recognizing private property as the only manner of land tenure in Spanish America—irrespective of if it meant indigenous or Spanish property. The significance of this shift in interpretation should not be underestimated: the theoretical origin of land rights in Spanish America went from being derivative, conditional rights bestowed on particular owners by the Crown in the 1940s to being preexistent, absolute ownership rights founded on the doctrinal distinction between territorial sovereignty and private property in the 1970s.

Ius commune, jurisdictional culture, and possession

As discussed above, the manner in which land rights are interpreted hinges upon how both law and the theoretical origins of land rights are characterized by the historian. The insistence by the historians of the derecho indiano on the existence of a monarchic state, on the importance of the Roman law distinction between public and private, and on the idea that legitimate land titles derived from state sanction, constructs an image of law and political power that resembles that of the nineteenth century. These assumptions about European law, however, have been starkly reassessed since the late 1970s by legal-historical research.Footnote5 The idea of the existence of an absolutist state in the Iberian Peninsula before the eighteenth century, as well as the colonial model of empire as an accurate depiction of the Iberian expansion to Asia, Africa, and America, has been wholly called into question.Footnote6 Likewise, António Manuel Hespanha has spoken of the contemporary distinction between public and private law as a ‘frequent anachronism’ attributed to Roman law or the European ius commune. In the latter normative systems, the voice ‘public’ was used topically, and ‘public law’ did not begin to constitute a doctrinal system until the late seventeenth century (Hespanha Citation2015).Footnote7 The question of how land rights were constituted, however, has not yet received such detailed attention. The aim of this section is to attempt a reconstruction of how land rights should be understood within the early-modern normative order once the anachronisms of the state and of the public/private distinction have been removed.

This article argues that the best way to understand land relations in Spanish America is not to begin with the regalía or the encomienda but with the institution of possession. First, this makes sense because it is a category that has begun to appear frequently in more recent historiographical research of Spanish America (e.g. Adorno Citation2007; Herzog Citation2015; Owensby Citation2008; Seed Citation1995). Second, it is central because it is an institution which does not arise from the power of the monarch, through grace, but is rather the outcome of discrete processes of demographic change, migration, and occupation.

To understand possession, however, it is necessary to briefly describe the broader normative universe in which it functioned as an important category: the ius commune. This was a complex normative corpus that was built up across almost six centuries, from the twelfth to the eighteenth. It may perhaps be best represented as the ongoing effort by learned jurists to arrange, in a rational and elegant fashion, a multiplicity of juridical orders (Hespanha Citation2013, 183). In a worldview in which the law was identified with a transcendental order of divine creation, human law was subordinated to the divine authority of aequitas and iustitia, and as such human law-making was always a process of revealing or declaring, but not creating, the law (Vallejo Citation2009, 7 ff.). This meant that alongside the unavailable orders of divine and natural law, which could not be modified by human will, laws could originate from multiple jurisdictional orders—including professional guilds, municipalities and city councils, kings, the church, communities, and magistrates. Different rules thus applied, variably, in the same territories and over the same populations, creating a complex set of overlapping juridical orders that were not hierarchically organized and, therefore, allowed for various simultaneous juridical solutions to any given circumstance (Vallejo Citation2009, 13). The ius commune was thus the manner in which jurists, throughout the early-modern period, sought to organize these norms, adapt them to changing circumstances, and provide insights into how diverse sources of law interacted in particular cases.

One manner of looking at this normative order within the Spanish American context is by rethinking the role of the Siete Partidas (Bravo Lira Citation1985). Originally composed in the thirteenth century, the Partidas’ influence grew in the Spanish Peninsula in the late fourteenth century and it became the most prominent doctrinal text in Spanish America in the course of the sixteenth century. It influenced the juridical practice not only in Spanish America, but also in the territories of the Portuguese Empire due to their reception in the Ordenações Alfonsinas of 1446. While Ots Capdequí (Citation1946, 78) viewed the Siete Partidas as the embodiment of Roman law in Spanish law, they have more recently been depicted as a ‘“nationalized” version of the ius commune’ (Decock Citation2013, 34) or, perhaps more accurately, as ‘a text of almost pure ius commune translated into the national language’ (Grossi Citation2010, 33). As a legislative text, the Siete Partidas drew mainly on the tradition of Roman and cannon law that had been informing European legal culture since the late Middle Ages. But crucially it placed law and political power within the framework of the ius commune and thus, though being an oeuvre handed down by the king, it clearly reflected the importance of the transcendental order in the creation of law and political power. The first line of the Prologue accordingly states: ‘God is beginning, middle, and end of all things, and without him nothing can be’ (Las Siete Partidas Citation1555, 1:3). Though the Siete Partidas cannot provide an exhaustive representation of the ‘overload’ of norms that characterized the early-modern period (Duve, Citation2020), it nevertheless offers a good entry point for understanding the normative background that informed juridical practice in the Americas.Footnote8

Within this juridical worldview no distinction existed between public and private law; the more important distinction was between general and special laws. As Alejandro Agüero has argued, in the 1555 glosses of Gregorio López to the Siete Partidas, the autonomy of norm-making by local jurisdictions was sustained alongside the power of the king or emperor to make general laws for the kingdom. Even in nineteenth-century editions of the Partidas, the ius commune principles persisted, allowing a conciliation of ‘the legislative power of the [prince] and the natural power of self-regulation assigned to every human community’ (Agüero Citation2016, 105). Local regulatory powers, such as statutes, custom, and privileges, whether written or not, were thus not subordinated to but rather stood alongside the general laws enacted by royal power, according to the principle that they were all jurisdictional acts that ultimately derived from the same substance of aequitas (Vallejo Citation2009, 12). This means that it is not possible for the historian to draw conclusions from the legislation of the Spanish Crown or emphasize a form of overarching ‘policy,’ since local ordinances and custom always operated simultaneously and had the power to supersede general laws (Tau Anzoátegui Citation2000).

Additionally, within the jurisdictional culture of the ius commune, ‘rules did not work as rigid abstract standards’ (Agüero Citation2016, 111). This was again related to the idea of aequitas, in which the functions of justice and law-making were tied to their correspondence with a natural order of things. Within this conception of law, existing states of affairs carried, in and of themselves, normative force; the task of law-making was thus to reveal the rules that already existed in social and natural life—and thus constituted a reflection of the divine order. The importance of factuality—of things as they are; the conservative force of the status quo—tied the function of law-making to that of interpretation. Laws could not be applied to any given situation. Rather, diverse juridical orders and a multiplicity of norms, which over centuries had accumulated to inform the juridical culture of the ius commune, had to be mobilized and adapted by the interpreter of law to the particular circumstances of the case at hand.Footnote9

It is within this normative worldview that the institution of possession must be understood. Possession is a complex juridical category due to its combination of factual and legal circumstances. It did not simply mean the physical taking hold of things but was rather a particular juridical situation that can be defined as existing states of affairs that were just or according to law. This can be seen in the way possession was defined in the Siete Partidas, as well as how it was distinguished from other forms of holding things. Law 1, title 30 of the Third Partida defines possession as the ‘lawful holding that man has in corporeal things with the help of body and mind’ (Las Siete Partidas Citation1555, 2:172v.). Possession thus required the ‘deliberate state of mind’ of acting as the owner of the thing alongside the bodily act of taking hold of it (Vizcaino Pérez Citation1784, 27). The distinction between physical holding and state of mind is relevant because it allows for distinguishing a possessor from tenants, settlers, or administrators who, though physically occupying the thing, do not possess ‘because they possess on behalf of another.’ Possession could also be acquired through tradition (traditio) or judicial resolution; but whoever entered the thing ‘by force, or stole it, or whichever way in which he holds it, does not therefore have true possession’ (Las Siete Partidas Citation1555, 2:174). Possession was therefore not the purely factual act of taking hold of a thing; instead, it was a specific legal relationship in which a title was generated through consolidated practices and it was a distinct category—different not only from dominion (señorío), but also from other forms of tenure.

The manner in which possession generated a title to land can be seen in other sections of the Partidas. Law 50, title 28 of the Third Partida, which relates to how dominion of land can be acquired, indicates that whoever ‘forsakes’ the land loses his dominion over it and henceforth ‘whoever first enters gains dominion of it’ (Las Siete Partidas Citation1555, 2:165). This conception is reinforced in procedural terms. Law 28, title 2 of the Third Partida indicates that in case of litigation,

Great benefit comes to the holders of things, whether they have them lawfully or not; because even though those who demand them say they are theirs, if they cannot prove their dominion of them, the tenure always remains with those who have them even though they cannot prove the right through which they have them. (Las Siete Partidas Citation1555, 2:10)

Solórzano Pereira also interpreted the functioning of these principles in the government of Spanish America when speaking of the composiciones carried out in the late sixteenth century. He praised the Real Cédula of 1591 for the fact that when it demanded the presentation of titles and measurements of the land it also advised the convenience of ‘not proceeding with a disposition of depriving and dispossessing the lands from their longstanding possessors and laborers’ (Solórzano Pereira Citation1648, 993). Solórzano noted that, by doing this, the Real Cédula of 1591 followed the ‘ancient wisdom’ that it would be best to ‘dissimulate […] on account of past time’ and profit from their labor in the future (Solórzano Pereira Citation1648, 993). The reference to the ‘ancient wisdom’ shows that the norm was rooted in longstanding doctrine and not in royal legislation. This manner of framing the problem corresponded with a juridical worldview which protected existing states of affairs and sets of relations that were recognized as such by the community (Bastias Saavedra Citation2018b).

The self-regulation of the community is what ultimately distinguished possession from other forms of occupation that could have been deemed unlawful. In judicial proceedings witnesses, often persons who had standing within the community, provided the evidence of rightful possession. These testimonies were often in and of themselves the title that proved the possessor’s ownership of the tracts of land (Bastias Saavedra Citation2018b, 17–18; Dias Paes Citation2018, 29 ff.). Further, as suggested in a recent study, the difference between possessors and squatters seems to have been solely based on the recognition of the local community. In a study of common lands in Santo Domingo, Andrew Walker has shown how new occupants who began to till and use common lands acquired the status of co-owners through the recognition of already established neighbors. Squatters, on the other hand, though fundamentally carrying out similar activities, such as tilling and using the land, lacked this social recognition (Walker Citation2018, 172 ff.). The fine line between lawful and unlawful occupation was ultimately based on communitarian self-regulation.

Before moving on, it must be noted that, given the importance of local specificity in the functioning of norms, generalizing about specific laws and institutions in Spanish America must be done carefully. Even though doctrine was in a constant process of adaptation to respond to shifts in practice, it cannot be said that any given doctrine was prevalent everywhere in Spanish America at any given time. This was coherent with the manner of norm-production in the early-modern world, in which new norms did not derogate older ones, thus leading to an ever-growing accumulation of legal rules. A consequence of this situation meant the simultaneous existence of contradictory norms and, even when new rules were intended to apply to specific circumstances, older rules could always be called upon due to the persistence of their condition as having arisen from aequitas (Vallejo Citation2009, 12). This, of course, tied the operation of law to the spaces in which it functioned, which could sometimes vary from one town or province to the next (Agüero Citation2016; Hespanha Citation2013), and was not necessarily tied to the chronology of doctrinal change. The flexibility of this kind of juridical order therefore calls upon the sensibility of the historian to be able to learn from the doctrinal texts while abstaining from considering them as rules that had to be applied henceforth. When studying a juridical culture tied to local circumstances, factualism, and casuistry, the historian must act accordingly, learning inductively from case to case, and respecting the local particularities in the jurisdictional operation of law.

Land relations and conflict in Spanish America

To compound the complexity of the juridical order prevalent in Spanish America, one must also consider the fact that the continent was a vast and diversely inhabited space, where Spanish occupation was fragmentary and discontinuous, and the question of land and claims to land necessarily involves the methodological problem of how the indigenous inhabitants conceived their own claims to the spaces in which they lived (see, for example, Owensby and Ross Citation2018). Furthermore, the structural openness of the ius commune allowed the asymmetrical, conditional, and discontinuous integration of indigenous norms, habits, and customs into the normative landscape of the Spanish expansion, making the interactions between conquerors and the native inhabitants of the continent a dynamic process of ‘hybridization between indigenous and non-indigenous justice systems’ (Duve Citation2017, 12).Footnote10 This, again, tied the functioning of norms to specific local contexts and periods, and understanding how land relations were normatively structured in Spanish America still requires abundant empirical research, particularly into the non-written sources of law.

Our understanding of the situation of land relations has, nevertheless, come a long way since the 1970s when Maríluz Urquijo noted that ‘most of the studies we rely on are based on the Recopilación de Indias or on other pertinent legal dispositions. Generally, judicial and notarial records that could shed light onto the application of law and the characteristics of custom have not been explored’ (Mariluz Urquijo Citation1970, 156–57). Recent historical research has concentrated on court records and other legal documentation found in the archives, but historians have also begun to focus particularly on the legal clauses found therein. Acts of possession, references to an immemorial past, quiet and pacific possession, titles, consent, knowledge, and absence of contradiction are all becoming part of a new vocabulary for historians interested in land relations in Spanish America.Footnote11 However, identifying these normatively laden words in the sources is still a much easier task than interpreting the norms and rules which organized the distribution of land across the continent. This means that getting the basic underlying assumptions right is important because it conditions the manner in which historians read their sources.

The discussion in the preceding sections has shown that the normative structure of the Spanish empire in the Americas can be characterized in two relatively irreconcilable manners and taking these divergent legal assumptions for granted can lead to widely contradictory interpretations of what is actually happening on the ground. Accordingly, the way contemporary historians treat the issue of land rights in Spanish America falls within a broad spectrum. On one extreme, there are those who argue that the Spaniards, upon their arrival in the sixteenth century, introduced individual, private property into America. In this conception, Spanish American land relations were characterized by a European law that came armed with an institutional apparatus of private law and native representations of land rights that were fundamentally different, based more on collective than on individual rights (Adorno Citation1993, 65; Graubart Citation2017, 63, 65; Míguez Núñez Citation2013, 26; Puente Luna Citation2008, 128). On the other extreme of the spectrum are those who, like Alan Greer (Citation2018), argue that there was no such thing as private property, either in Europe or in America, until the late eighteenth century. Most authors fall somewhere in between these positions. Very few authors, however, explicitly state what they understand to be the theoretical origins of land rights in Spanish America, and those who do usually adopt some version of the derecho indiano tradition.

Ots Capdequí’s influence is found, for example, in Agustín Parise’s (2017) characterization of the early modern Spanish American land regime as an ‘allocation paradigm of ownership.’ According to Parise, Spanish monarchs held all discovered territories in regalía, which gave them something resembling ‘primordial ownership,’ ‘eminent domain,’ or dominium and jurisdiction over the American territories, and as such ‘any possible rights of others on the land had to be granted by the monarch, by means of a grace (gracia)’ (Parise Citation2017, 65). Native Americans and European settlers could obtain individual private ownership of lands through the system of mercedes, while common ownership of lands was allotted by the Crown through the ‘transplantation’ of institutions from the Peninsula (ejidos, dehesas, propios, montes, pastos, among others) or through the creation of pueblos (Parise Citation2017, 95–125). Brian Owensby follows Ots Capdequí’s characterization of the Spanish American land regime even more closely when he argues that the Crown’s conception of property as a ‘social function’ clashed with that of individual Spaniards in Mexico, who ‘appear to have been moving toward a more individualized, Roman conception of ownership’ (Owensby Citation2008, 94). Elsewhere, in a sense actualizing Ots Capdequí’s argument about the differences between Spanish law and the derecho propiamente indiano, Owensby reconstructs the difference between land tenure in Spain and land tenure in the Americas. While ‘the law of property relations in Spain […] was fairly orderly,’ he argues, there was ‘no order to property relations’ in the New World (Owensby Citation2008, 96–97). This is partly because, in the encounter between indigenous and Spanish property norms, the Crown found itself trying to satisfy the Spanish demand for property and the indigenous demand for protection of their possessions.

When it comes to justifying the theoretical origins of indigenous land rights, Góngora’s influence is less straightforward, since most of the authors who make the point about their preexistence do not mention him among their references. The main inspirations for Góngora’s discussion on the encomienda and the question of the title by which the indigenous populations held their land were the questions on monarchic authority raised by Francisco de Vitoria and others (Pagden Citation1987, 82 ff.). Góngora saw the centrality of the encomienda because, in his view, it allowed the Crown to solve, at once, the pragmatic problem of populating the American territory and the normative problem created after the controversies of 1511 on the legitimacy of the Spanish claims to the Indies. The system of the encomienda, for Góngora, safeguarded the liberty and the lands of the indigenous peoples while facilitating Spanish settlement by providing a controlled system of tribute in compensation for services to the Crown. In this way, the system of the encomienda

… is an eminently ‘colonial’ salaried service provided by free men, owners of their lands [the natives], which benefits the settlement of the Spanish population without the law suppressing their situation of freedom and capacity to have property, nor modifying the juridical status of their lands. (Góngora Citation1951, 106)

Alan Greer (Citation2018, 2), who has argued forcefully, and correctly, against the naïve and anachronistic view of property with which historians tend to write the history of the New World, has nevertheless taken up some of the ideas traditionally endorsed by the derecho indiano. Almost paraphrasing Góngora, he argues that, in the context of New Spain, ‘Native property was […] primordial, and imperial authorities accepted the fact that its existence and legitimacy predated any European property’ (Greer Citation2018, 131–32). Elsewhere, when discussing the Mexican conquest, Greer (Citation2018, 72–73) adds that ‘Cortés did not grant land to the Indian pueblos and their caciques, nor did Charles V: they both basically accepted the prior existence and legitimacy of native property.’ While he does not indicate the source of these claims, in another passage Greer (Citation2018, 110) refers to Owensby’s book to support his statement that ‘courts treated Indian community lands as primordial.’ In his study of indigenous amparos and litigation, Owensby (Citation2008, 92) attributes this doctrine to Francisco de Vitoria, whom he credits with putting forth the idea that, since the original inhabitants of America had been in possession of their lands before conquest, ‘they could not “be dispossessed without due cause,”’ making indigenous rights to their land ‘unassailable at law.’

The questions that arise from these characterizations include how the historian expects conflicts over land to be decided under these conditions and what this says about law more generally. The assumption appears to be that since law had defined a place for either Spanish or indigenous property this also meant that ‘property’ was somehow protected either through the judicial process or through political recourse. Yet what historians are confronted with in the use of judicial sources reveals something quite different, riddled with ‘countless occupations, usurpations, and sales’ (Owensby Citation2008), leading to ‘confusion’ and ‘ambiguities’ (Graubart Citation2017; Stavig Citation2000). These kinds of statements, which are quite common, reveal the historian’s underlying expectations about what law is and does or, at least, should do: protect property.Footnote12 However, as has been said, law in Spanish America was not structured to guarantee the application of rules, laws, or norms, but was rather a continuously open process of normative production in which primacy was given to existing states of affairs. This meant that the ‘legality’ of acts could not simply be derived from the bodies of laws because exceptions to the rule, under certain conditions, were always possible. Although it was commonly understood, for example, that holdings in mayorazgo or of the Church were inalienable, this rule could always be circumvented given that there was a cause of necessity, utility, piety, or other, and certain formal and solemn requirements were fulfilled (Dios Citation2015, esp. 52 ff.). These requisites of form ultimately justified changes to situations that were otherwise considered to be legally immutable. Salustiano de Dios argues that Castillo de Bobadilla went as far as arguing that cause of necessity could alter longstanding precepts not only of human law, but also of divine and natural law (Dios Citation2015, 68). In such a normative system, it must be stressed, law was not concerned primarily with protecting ‘property.’

While the focus on judicial practice brought about by the more recent historiography is certainly important, its overall assumptions of how law functioned and how land rights were asserted needs correcting. The granting of titles through merced, for example, did not create perpetual and judicially enforceable rights to land because, as grace, once they were granted, they became situations of justice, which strived to preserve the natural and social order, and were thus submitted to the contingencies of experience. The merced was, in this sense, one title among many others, but a holder of a merced could not claim the land thus granted as his own if it had not been possessed or if it had later been forsaken. The administration of law could not simply presume that titles granted rights because, as we have discussed, norms could not simply be applied deductively to the cases but had to be derived from them. In addition, according to the logic of the early-modern juridical culture, the exercise of jurisdiction and the administration of justice occurred in situations of conflict resolution. This gave the procedural level of judicial practice an important deliberative role, which included not only the intervention of norms, but also the ascertainment of the facts of the case by hearing the affected parties (Agüero Citation2007, 41–43). Affected parties could include not only the litigants, but also heirs, neighbors, members of the community, and anyone who stood to suffer injury from any changes to the status quo.

Attention to this aspect of judicial practice is therefore central to understanding how certain decisions were reached. Titles were important in early-modern law, but so were settled social situations—situations conceived as such by the community. References to an immemorial past, as well as clauses often used in judicial and scribal documents, which indicate consent, knowledge, and absence of contradiction thus refer to the ‘necessary and ongoing search for consensus on what could be considered just or fair according to local circumstances’ (Agüero Citation2016, 113). Elsewhere, it has been argued that ownership and possession were closely intertwined because owners as well as dimensions of pieces of land could only be determined by recourse to the history of the space which resided in the social knowledge and memory of the community (Bastias Saavedra Citation2018b). Ward Stavig’s (Citation2000) interesting case study on landholdings in rural Cuzco also highlights many examples that reflect these communitarian aspects of securing rights to land. The value of the concept of possession is that, ultimately, it sheds light on the customary arrangements achieved by local communities and the legal recognition given to such settled states of affairs.

Conclusions

Making sense of the important role of possession in the structuring of land relations in early-modern Spanish America calls for a better understanding of the more general way law functioned in the context of the ius commune. It also requires abandoning the statist and legalist mindsets that shape our contemporary representations of the relation between persons and things. In a sense, this means provincializing European law; the Spaniards that came to America, and their legal representation of the world, were not modern—they were not rational economic actors and their worldview was not utilitarian and scientific. And they certainly did not bring with them an image of individual private property or an institutional apparatus of private law.

Rather, the juridical worldview introduced into the New World was tied to the primacy of divine creation and theological notions such as aequitas and iustitia. The application of law was also less a courtroom procedural, with lawyerly argumentation and clever uses of legal artifices, than a casuistic, commonsense manner of finding solutions that different kinds of magistrates would use to restore the social peace according to the very specific conditions of the local community (Tau Anzoátegui Citation1992). The Crown, in particular, could not neatly dispose of and organize its territorial domains through laws and ordinances, could not enact sweeping colonial policy, and could not govern through legislation, because the body of norms tended to accumulate throughout the centuries, deriving from multiple sources of both divine and human law, and the norms themselves would change and adapt to local social practices (Hespanha Citation2006). The often ‘confusing’ and ‘ambiguous’ character of judicial decisions found across the literature on Spanish America is due to the fact that the European ius commune was structurally bound to local and personal jurisdictions and was thus organized in a much more (micro-)spatial than chronological manner. Ultimately, in order to interpret judicial sources on land relations in Spanish America, it is essential to understand the peculiar normative order in which the legal protection of possession actually made sense. Possession was a central juridical category in a worldview in which existing states of affairs carried, in and of themselves, normative value.

Finally, indicating the anachronistic use of private property is not simply a trivial technical debate in the interest of legal historians. The fundamental problem with the anachronistic use of the concept of property when speaking of land relations in Spanish America should not be understated; however well intentioned, it serves as an implicit narrative device to highlight the ‘modernity’ of European man in contrast to the ‘otherness’ of the indigenous experience. It temporalizes the indigenous and the European experience in the early-modern Spanish American world, and fundamentally transforms the notion of hybridization into what the indigenous populations gained and lost with the ‘arrival’ of modern conceptions of property. This, ultimately, serves as a way of concealing the alterity of the juridical worldview that characterized the European expansion into the New World, which did not entail a framework of judicial protection of private property rights. Instead, it tied land rights to effective possession and use, as well as to communitarian relations which were seen as a manifestation of the religious obligations of the king and his people to cultivate and populate the land.

Biographical note

Manuel Bastias Saavedra is a researcher at the Max-Planck-Institut für europäische Rechtsgeschichte in Frankfurt am Main, Germany. He currently coordinates the joint project ‘Glocalising Normativities: A Global Legal History (15th to 21st Century).’ He received a PhD in history from the Freie Universität Berlin, where he is also a lecturer. His main research interests are colonial peripheries of the Spanish empire, land tenure and local law, and political and social movements in 20th-century Latin America. He was an Alexander von Humboldt Fellow at the Universität Bremen and at the Universidade Nova de Lisboa. He has published articles in, among others, the Journal of Modern European History, Iberoamericana, Archiv für Sozialgeschichte, Historia Crítica, and Rechtsgeschichte – Legal History (Rg).

Notes

1 In its ethnographic sense, understood not only as a space where documents are stored but where knowledge is produced. On this, see Stoler Citation2002.

2 For some recent related literature, see, for example, Ebright Citation2014; Míguez Núñez Citation2013; Parise Citation2017.

3 For a critical overview, see Garriga Citation2017; Hespanha Citation2017; Nuzzo Citation2015.

4 Ots Capdequí is aware of the anachronism he uses when referring to this as indicating a ‘social function’ of property.

5 Two books any historian interested in early-modern law should have in her library are Grossi Citation1995 and Hespanha Citation2015.

6 For a brief overview, also Bastias Saavedra Citation2018a.

7 Perhaps the best critical essay against using both the concept of state and the private/public dichotomy in the early-modern period is Garriga Citation2004.

8 For recent studies on the ius commune in the Portuguese context, see Cabral Citation2016.

9 A good example is the way religious and theological norms were used in adjudicating cases in Spanish America. See Herzog Citation1995.

10 A very nuanced approach to Spanish-indigenous interactions can be found in García Ruiz Citation2015.

11 Examples can be found in Bastias Saavedra Citation2018b; Graubart Citation2017; Herzog Citation2013; Owensby Citation2008; Stavig Citation2000. For a similar perspective in the case of Portuguese America, see Dias Paes Citation2017.

12 Tamar Herzog (Citation2013, 304) approaches this problem in a different manner, by studying the processes of ‘translation and mediation’ that ultimately reveal the underlying rules that were being constructed on the ground.

References

  • Adorno, Rolena. 1993. The genesis of Felipe Guaman Poma de Ayala’s Nueva corónica y buen gobierno. Colonial Latin American Review 2 (1–2): 53–92. doi: 10.1080/10609169308569807
  • Adorno, Rolena.. 2007. The polemics of possession in Spanish American narrative. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Agüero, Alejandro. 2007. Las categorías básicas de la cultura jurisdiccional. In De justicia de jueces a justicia de leyes: hacia la España de 1870, edited by Marta Lorente, 21–58. Madrid: Consejo General del Poder Judicial.
  • Agüero, Alejandro.. 2016. Local law and localization of law: Hispanic legal tradition and colonial culture (16th–18th centuries). In Spatial and temporal dimensions for legal history: research experiences and itineraries, edited by Massimo Meccarelli and María J. Solla Sastre, 101–29. Frankfurt am Main: Max Planck Institute for European Legal History.
  • Bastias Saavedra, Manuel. 2018a. Jurisdictional autonomy and the autonomy of law: end of empire and the functional differentiation of law in 19th-century Latin America. Rechtsgeschichte 26: 325–37. doi: 10.12946/rg26/325-337
  • Bastias Saavedra, Manuel.. 2018b. The lived space: possession, ownership, and land sales on the Chilean frontier (Valdivia, 1790–1830). Historia Crítica 67: 3–21. doi: 10.7440/histcrit67.2018.01
  • Blaufarb, Rafe. 2016. The great demarcation. The French Revolution and the invention of modern property. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Borde, Jean, and Mario Góngora. 1956. Evolución de la propiedad rural en el Valle del Puangue. Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
  • Bravo Lira, Bernardino. 1985. Vigencia de las Partidas en Chile. Revista de Estudios Histórico-Jurídicos 10: 43–105.
  • Cabral, Gustavo Machado. 2016. Ius Commune in Portuguese America: criminal issues on local canon law in the ‘First Constitutions of the Diocese of Bahia’ (1707). GLOSSAE. European Journal of Legal History 13: 328–41.
  • Cabral, Gustavo Machado.. 2017. Literatura jurídica na idade moderna. As decisiones no reino de Portugal (séculos XVI e XVII). Rio de Janeiro: Editora Lumen Juris.
  • Decock, Wim. 2013. Theologians and contract law. The moral transformation of the Ius Commune (ca. 1500–1650). Leiden: Nijhoff Publishers.
  • Dias Paes, Mariana A. 2017. Sobre origens, continuidades e criações: A posse da liberdade nos decisionistas portugueses (sécs. XVI–XVIII) e no direito da escravidão (séc. XIX). In Actas del XIX Congreso del Instituto Internacional de Historia del Derecho Indiano: Berlin 2016, edited by Thomas Duve, 1379–406. Madrid: Dykinson.
  • Dias Paes, Mariana A.. 2018. Escravos e terras entre posses e títulos. A construção social do direito de propriedades no Brasil (1835–1889). Doctoral dissertiation, Universidade de São Paulo.
  • Dios, Salustiano de. 2015. Representación doctrinal de la propiedad en los juristas de la Corona de Castilla (1480–1640). In Seis estudios sobre historia de la propiedad, edited by Salustiano de Dios, 17–68. Salamanca: Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca.
  • Duve, Thomas. 2017. Indigenous rights in Latin America: a legal historical perspective. Max Planck Institute for European Legal History Research Paper Series 2017-02, accessed 10 April 2019, http://ssrn.com/abstract=2976301.
  • Duve, Thomas.. 2020. Pragmatic normative literature and the production of normative knowledge in the early modern Iberian empires in the 16th–17th centuries. In Knowledge of the pragmatici: legal and moral theological literature and the formation of early modern Ibero-America, edited by Thomas Duve and Otto Danwerth. Leiden: Brill.
  • Ebright, Malcolm. 2014. Advocates for the oppressed: Hispanos, Indians, Genízaros, and their land in New Mexico. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.
  • García Gallo, Alfonso. 1970. Metodología de la historia del Derecho Indiano. Santiago: Editorial Jurídica de Chile.
  • García Ruiz, Luis J. 2015. La territorialidad de la República de Indios de Orizaba. Entre la separación de los sujetos y la preponderancia española: 1740–1828. Historia Mexicana 64 (4): 1415–61. doi: 10.24201/hm.v64i4.3153
  • Garriga, Carlos. 2004. Orden jurídico y poder político en el Antiguo Régimen. Istor. Revista de historia internacional 16: 3–44.
  • Garriga, Carlos.. 2017. ¿De qué hablamos cuando hablamos de Derecho Indiano? In Actas del XIX Congreso del Instituto Internacional de Historia del Derecho Indiano, edited by Thomas Duve, 1:223–48. Madrid: Dykinson.
  • Góngora, Mario. 1951. El estado en el Derecho Indiano: época de fundación 1492–1570. Santiago: Universidad de Chile.
  • Gordley, James, and Ugo Mattei. 1996. Protecting possession. The American Journal of Comparative Law 44 (2): 293–334. doi: 10.2307/840711
  • Graubart, Karen B. 2017. Shifting landscapes: heterogeneous conceptions of land use and tenure in the Lima valley. Colonial Latin American Review 26 (1): 62–84. doi: 10.1080/10609164.2017.1287328
  • Greer, Allan. 2018. Property and dispossession: natives, empires and land in early modern North America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Grossi, Paolo. 1995. El orden jurídico medieval. Madrid: Marcial Pons.
  • Grossi, Paolo.. 2010. A history of European law. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Herzog, Tamar. 1995. Sobre la cultura jurídica de la América colonial (siglos XVI–XVIII). Anuario de Historia del Derecho Español 65: 903–12.
  • Herzog, Tamar.. 2013. Colonial law and ‘native customs’: indigenous land rights in colonial Spanish America. The Americas 69 (3): 303–21. doi: 10.1353/tam.2013.0016
  • Herzog, Tamar.. 2015. Frontiers of possession: Spain and Portugal in Europe and the Americas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Hespanha, António M. 2006. Porque é que existe e em que é que consiste umdireito colonial brasileiro. Quaderni Fiorentini per la Storia del PensieroGiuridicoModerno 35: 59–81.
  • Hespanha, António M.. 2013. Uncommon laws: law in the extreme peripheries of an early modern empire. Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte: Germanistische Abteilung 130 (1): 180–204. doi: 10.7767/zrgga.2013.130.1.180
  • Hespanha, António M.. 2015. Como os juristas viam o mundo. 1550–1750: Direitos, estados, pessoas, coisas, contratos, ações, e crimes. Lisbon : s.n.
  • Hespanha, António M.. 2017. O ‘direito de Índias’ no contexto da historiografia das colonizações ibéricas. In Actas del XIX Congreso del Instituto Internacional de Historia del Derecho Indiano, edited by Thomas Duve, 1:43–83. Madrid: Dykinson.
  • Las Siete Partidas del rey Don Alfonso el Sabio. 1555. Vols. 1–3. Salamanca: Andrea de Portonaris.
  • Levene, Ricardo. 1916. Introducción al estudio del Derecho Indiano. Buenos Aires: Imprenta Escoffier, Caracciolo y Cía.
  • Mariluz Urquijo, José M. 1968. El régimen de la tierra en el Derecho Indiano. Buenos Aires: Editorial Perrot.
  • Mariluz Urquijo, José M.. 1970. La propiedad en el derecho indiano. Revista Chilena de Historia del Derecho 6: 154–57.
  • Míguez Núñez, Rodrigo. 2013. Terra di scontri: alterazioni e rivendicazioni del diritto alla terra nelle Ande centrali. Milan: Giuffrè Editore.
  • Nuzzo, Luigi. 2015. Between America and Europe: the strange case of the derecho indiano. In New horizons in Spanish colonial law: contributions to transnational early modern legal history, edited by Thomas Duve and Heikki Pihlajamäki, 161–91. Frankfurt am Main: Max Planck Institute for European Legal History.
  • Ots Capdequí, José M. 1946. El régimen de la tierra en hispanoamérica. Ciudad Trujillo [Santo Domingo]: Editora Montalvo.
  • Ots Capdequí, José M.. 1959. España en América: el régimen de tierras en la época colonial. Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Económica.
  • Owensby, Brian. 2008. Empire of law and Indian justice in colonial Mexico. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
  • Owensby, Brian, and Richard Ross. 2018. Justice in a new world: negotiating legal intelligibility in British, Iberian, and indigenous America. New York: New York University Press.
  • Pagden, Anthony. 1987. Dispossessing the barbarian: the language of Spanish Thomism and the debate over property rights of the American Indians. In The languages of political theory in early-modern Europe, edited by Anthony Pagden, 79–98. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Parise, Agustín. 2017. Ownership paradigms in American civil law jurisdictions: manifestations of the shifts in the legislation of Louisiana, Chile, and Argentina (16th–20th centuries). Leiden: Brill; Nijhoff. doi: 10.1163/9789004338203
  • Puente Luna, José Carlos de la. 2008. Cuando el ‘punto de vista nativo’ no es el punto de vista de los nativos: Felipe Guaman Poma de Ayala y la apropiación de tierras en el Perú colonial. Bulletin de l'Institut Français d’Études Andines 37 (1): 123–49. doi: 10.4000/bifea.3357
  • Seed, Patricia. 1995. Ceremonies of possession in Europe’s conquest of the New World, 1492–1640. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Solórzano Pereira, Juan de. 1648. Política Indiana: sacada en lengua castellana de los dos tomos del derecho i govierno municipal de las Indias occidentales que mas copiosamente escribio en la latina. Madrid: Diego Díaz de la Carrera.
  • Stavig, Ward. 2000. Ambiguous visions: nature, law, and culture in indigenous-Spanish land relations in colonial Peru. Hispanic American Historical Review 80 (1): 77–111. doi: 10.1215/00182168-80-1-77
  • Stoler, Ann Laura. 2002. Colonial archives and the arts of governance. Archival Science 2 (1–2): 87–109. doi: 10.1007/BF02435632
  • Tau Anzoátegui, Víctor. 1982. ¿Qué fue el Derecho Indiano? Buenos Aires: Editorial Perrot.
  • Tau Anzoátegui, Víctor.. 1992. Cauismo y sistema: indagación histórica sobre el espíritu del Derecho Indiano. Buenos Aires: Instituto de Investigaciones de Historia del Derecho.
  • Tau Anzoátegui, Víctor.. 2000. El poder de la costumbre. Estudios sobre el derecho consuetudinario en América hispana hasta la Emancipación. Madrid: Fundación Larramendi.
  • Vallejo, Jesús. 2009. El cáliz de plata: articulación de órdenes jurídicos en la jurisprudencia del ius commune. Revista de Historia del Derecho 38: 1–13.
  • Vizcaino Pérez, Vicente. 1784. Compendio del derecho público y comun de España ó de las leyes de las Siete Partidas 2. Madrid: Ibarra.
  • Walker, Andrew J. 2018. Strains of unity: emancipation, property, and the post-revolutionary state in Haitian Santo Domingo, 1822–1844. Doctoral dissertation, University of Michigan. Retrieved from file://svmw10/homes$/bastias/Downloads/ajwalk_1%20(1).pdf
  • Zavala, Silvio. 1940. De encomiendas y propiedad territorial en algunas regiones de la América española. Mexico City: Antigua Librería Robredo, de José Porrúa e Hijos.