490
Views
38
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Feature Articles

Arrow's Theorem of the Deductible with Heterogeneous Beliefs

Pages 15-35 | Published online: 21 Jul 2016
 

Abstract

In Arrow's classical problem of demand for insurance indemnity schedules, it is well-known that the optimal insurance indemnification for an insurance buyer—or decision maker (DM)—is a deductible contract when the insurer is a risk-neutral Expected-Utility (EU) maximizer and when the DM is a risk-averse EU maximizer. In Arrow's framework, however, both parties share the same probabilistic beliefs about the realizations of the underlying insurable loss. This article reexamines Arrow's problem in a setting where the DM and the insurer have different subjective beliefs. Under a requirement of compatibility between the insurer's and the DM's subjective beliefs, we show the existence and monotonicity of optimal indemnity schedules for the DM. The belief compatibility condition is shown to be a weakening of the assumption of a monotone likelihood ratio. In the latter case, we show that the optimal indemnity schedule is a variable deductible schedule, with a state-contingent deductible that depends on the state of the world only through the likelihood ratio. Arrow's classical result is then obtained as a special case.

Notes

In Aumann's framework, an event is said to be common knowledge if both individuals know it, if each individual knows that the other individual knows it, if each individual knows that other individuals knows that the former knows it, and so on.

I am grateful to Rachel Huang for pointing out to me the analysis done in Huang et al. (Citation2002). I came to be aware of the latter paper after the completion of this present work.

A finite measure η on a measurable space is said to be nonatomic if for any with η(A) > 0, there is some such that BA and 0 < η(B) < η(A).

By the theory of equimeasurable rearrangements described in Appendix A.

For instance, if QX− 1 has atoms.

Let μ1 and μ2 be two probability measures on a measurable space . The probability measure μ2 is said to be absolutely continuous with respect to the probably measure μ1 (denoted by μ2 ≪ μ1) if for all with μ1(C) = 0, one has μ2(C) = 0. This does not rule out the existence of some such that μ2(D) = 0 but μ1(D) > 0.

Note that the optimal contract described in Theorem 4.6 is can be seen as a contract that combines a straight deductible and a (variable) co-insurance.

By two “changes of variable,” as in (Aliprantis and Border Citation2006, Theorem 13.46), and using the definition of f and g as Radon-Nikodým derivatives of PX− 1 and QX− 1, respectively, with respect to the Lebesgue measure.

This choice of x is possible because if it were not, then that would contradict the fact that Y1 and Y2 are identically distributed for P.

For any , the Dirac delta function centered at a is zero everywhere except at a where it is infinite. Moreover, ∫a + ϵa − ϵφ(t)δ(ta) dt = φ(a), for any ϵ > 0 and for any function φ. See, e.g., Bracewell (Citation2000, Ch. 5).

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 114.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.