12,951
Views
25
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Research Articles

Erosion or decay? Conceptualizing causes and mechanisms of democratic regression

Pages 43-62 | Received 29 May 2020, Accepted 09 Sep 2020, Published online: 14 Oct 2020

ABSTRACT

Democratic regression has become a worrying phenomenon in the last years. Social science has provided a variety of explanations why democratic regimes have lost democratic regime quality. Against this backdrop, I take stock of the recent literature by putting forward two important analytical distinctions that we should make more explicit. First, I propose to classify our current explanations along the source where the cause for the malaise originated. By doing so, I introduce a distinction between erosion and decay type of arguments. While the former is a gradual process that is caused exogenously – like wind or water hitting a stone – the latter is caused endogenously – like the half-life in nuclear decay processes. Second, I draw a distinction between the endogenous or exogenous roots of the cause and the subsequent causal mechanism that connects the cause with the outcome. I outline the need for dissecting a causal mechanism into its constitutive components and highlight its underlying dimensions of temporality. Throughout the article, I use empirical case material as well as relevant secondary literature to illustrate these points.

Many countries around the globe suffer currently from democratic regression, broadly defined as a loss of democratic quality.Footnote1 These developments can be observed in a variety of places and dominate today’s headlines. Among many examples, Hungary and Poland’s democratic quality has deteriorated as well as in Erdoğan’s Turkey, Russia under Putin, Duterte in the Philippines, or the United States of America under Trump.

Democratic regression is normatively worrying and empirical widespread, so that it does not surprise that the finest minds of comparative democratization have lately turned their eyes to these developments and have begun to dig deeper for theoretically saturated explanations.Footnote2 Yet, with notable exceptions,Footnote3 the current state of the art is – to my reading – densely populated with in-depth case studies that seek to explain rather the particular, but that lack theoretical and conceptual coherence. This article is motivated by reviewing these insightful accounts and classifying them in a novel and hopefully helpful fashion that seeks to facilitate dialogue across individual cases. As such, the article can be understood as a taking stock endeavour with a constructive intent.

To be clear, there is an abundance of explanatory factors that are currently discussed. These factors are usually combined into bigger clusters, often ordered along the basic social science distinction between economic, societal, cultural, and political factors,Footnote4 or, alternatively, between supply-side and demand-side explanations.Footnote5 A more fine-grained distinction is made by Waldner and Lust.Footnote6 They use the classic democratization theories that have been advanced in the last decades and turn them on their head for explaining the reverse trend of autocratization. In this light, they distinguish between agency-based theories, political culture approaches, institutionalist theories, theories of political economy, social structures and coalitional arguments, and international factors. Tying different explanatory factors to the wealth of democratization studies is intuitive, but represents, of course, only an approximation that, above all, needs to assume a symmetrical argumentation: When X has led to democratization, the absence of X must lead to autocratization. Remarkably, the editors of this special issue suggest to further distinguish between proximate and deep causes of democratic regressions,Footnote7 harking back to Mayr’sFootnote8 influential distinction on the nature of causation in biology.

In this article, I take a different stance. I suggest that the basic distinction should be made between endogenous and exogenous factors,Footnote9 proposing that the source of the cause could constitute a helpful axis along which we could classify arguments about democratic regression. This contribution explicitly adopts a historical institutionalist perspective and argues that the institutionalist repertoire of explaining change is a well-suited starting point for sorting our current explanations of democratic regression. More specifically, I use the approach by Thelen and colleaguesFootnote10 on gradual institutional change as a theoretical springboard to distinguish between two forms of gradual change. Borrowing metaphors from natural science, I draw a distinction between erosion and decay processes. While decay is endogenously caused, erosion is an exogenously driven process. I argue that it is of utmost importance to clarify in the first place where the causal driver for democratic regression is actually located. This is the major axis along which I classify the causes of democratic regression. This distinction has important implications not only for adequately explaining the empirical phenomenon of democratic regression, but also for sound policy advice.

The distinction between erosion or decay arguments has also important repercussions on the design of the causal mechanism that translates the causes to the outcome. As such, the causal mechanism is either being rooted in an endogenous or exogenous cause. In other words, the causes constitute the anchor points from which one needs to further develop the inner logic and unfolding of the concrete causal mechanisms. I outline the need for dissecting a causal mechanism into its components and highlight underlying dimensions of temporality. As such, I pay emphasis on marking a difference between the cause X and the causal mechanism M, arguing that they should be kept separate for analytical precision.

The same argument about analytical precision applies for an obvious concern. A complex phenomenon like democratic regression is not mono-causal. There is not only one cause that triggers one causal mechanism that leads to the outcome of democratic regression. Rather, it is a conjunction of several streams and mechanisms that might partially overlap temporally and substantially, that affect each other, be it in a mutually reinforcing or mutually undermining way. Yet, I think it is safe to argue that acknowledging the complex interplay of these mechanisms does not prevent us from disentangling them from each other. In contrast, analytical precision demands to dissect them form each other. As such, I see the proposed distinction between (a) endogenous and exogenous causes and (b) causes and causal mechanisms as important steps in taking apart complex explanations.

The article is structured as follows. In section II, I will go back to the historical neo-institutionalist debate about explaining institutional change. I attempt to bring their toolbox back into the debate, enriching our understanding of democratic regression. Based on this discussion, I propose in section III a new axis along which we should classify our arguments. Depending on the source where the causes for the malaise originates, I distinguish between exogenous erosion and endogenous decay arguments. In section IV, I then zoom into the causal mechanisms M. I conclude in section V by first synthesizing major insights of this article and then highlighting future research avenues.

The historical institutionalist toolkit: forms of gradual change

In this article, I draw on the rich toolkit of historical neo-institutionalism.Footnote11 Historical institutionalism provides not only an ample, but also a well-sorted arsenal in explaining change. Against this backdrop, I argue that it can be made fruitful for systematically thinking about processes of democratic regressions.

Yet, it should be noted that historical neo-institutionalism has long been plagued by a stability bias.Footnote12 Using its typical instrumentarium, it is easier for historical institutionalists to explain the long phases of institutional reproduction than to actually account for changes. The “punctuated equilibrium”, the dualism of path dependency and critical juncture, is almost essential knowledge for this theoretical approach.Footnote13 In most accounts, long phases of institutional stability that are often portrayed as being based on increasing returns to scaleFootnote14 are interrupted by brief moments of change in which decisive action is taken in either direction.Footnote15 The Achilles heel of this explanatory dualism, however, has always been how the brief interruptions that enable change come about in the first place. This task was often relegated to the mere occurrence of critical junctures.

Against this backdrop, it is particularly the research agenda of Kathleen Thelen and colleagues who challenged this approach.Footnote16 She deviates from the “common wisdom” of historical institutionalism in two important regards. First, she is more interested in explaining how change comes about – rather than assuming that there are windows of opportunities in which “permissive” and “productive conditions” make change likely.Footnote17 Second, she is more interested in gradual forms of change.Footnote18 While the “punctuated equilibrium” approach focuses on a sudden interruption, the Thelen agenda adopts a longer time horizon. The duration as the temporal length of a process in which change takes place is extended. Framing it differently: while the longue durée that is characteristic for many works in the historical institutionalism tradition refers often to the development of the outcome after the critical juncture is taken, this approach uses extended and stretched periods of time in order to explain how the outcome came actually about over time.

I think it is fair to argue that the Thelen research agenda could be divided into two broad parts.Footnote19 Particularly in her work with Streeck, Thelen accounts for different forms of change.Footnote20 In her work with Mahoney, she further develops the idea by adding types of “change agents” that stand behind these forms of change.Footnote21 Five forms of gradual change have been identified by Thelen and her co-authors: displacement, layering, drift, conversion, and exhaustion. Displacement sees the gradual emergence of new models that call into question old ones; layering is the “active sponsorship of amendments, additions, or revisions to an existing set of institutions”; drift is the slippage of an institution; conversion is the redeployment of an old institution to a new purpose; and exhaustion refers to the overextension and gradual breakdown of an institution.Footnote22 These five types aptly capture the broad variety of gradual change processes. Yet, these five processes are rather descriptive and procedural in nature and answer the question of how change unfolds, but not why these processes take place.

The respective actors behind (four of) these five processes are specified in a later work.Footnote23 Layering processes are driven by subversive actors. The most conducive environment for the emergence of these actors is a weak institution with low discretionary leeway for the actors, but one in which the political context has strong veto powers. Displacement sees insurrectionaries as major actors that act also in weak institutions with a lot of discretionary leeway, but with rather weak outside veto points. Drift is driven by parasitic symbionts that act under a tight institution with low leeway and in a strong context with veto power. Lastly, Thelen and Mahoney assume opportunistic actors in a tight institution, but with a weak veto environment.

Endogenous or exogenous causes for democratic regression?

I take these insightful considerations of historical neo-institutionalism as a theoretical starting point. The different forms and actors of gradual processes that recent research has addressed give answers to the questions of how change takes place, by whom change is performed, and under what circumstances these developments are to be expected. I add to this insightful discussion the source of the cause, distinguishing between exogenous and endogenous causes.

Erosion and decay arguments

While the above discussed literature is usually interpreted as forms of endogenous gradual change, the distinction between endogenous and exogenous causes can already be read into it.Footnote24 Layering, for example, is better to be understood if the change comes from without and is added onto an old institution. Similarly, exhaustion invokes an understanding of endogenous decay. When it comes to displacement, drift, and conversion, the picture becomes more complicated. Expressis verbis, Streeck and Thelen remain ambivalent about exogenous and endogenous drivers for these types of change. Displacement, for example, can happen either due to a “rediscovery or activation of previously suppressed or suspended possibilities” or due to an “invasion” that is characterized by a “supplanting of indigenous institutions and practices with foreign ones”.Footnote25 The former would be an example for endogenous gradual change, the latter for an exogenous one. In my language, the former is an endogenous decay that needs to be analytically separated from exogenous erosion.

Literally, endogenous and exogenous to an institution means that the cause for a process is not only located within or outside the institution under study, but that the cause is also generated within or outside an institution. This driver for change works so from the outside in – or vice versa. I suggest distinguishing between internally generated causes and externally generated causes, the former associated with forms of decay, the latter associated with forms of erosion. Borrowing from natural sciences, I argue that erosion-type arguments use a different explanatory architecture than decay-type arguments. While erosion is a phenomenon in which wind or water hits a stone, making it porous over time and carrying gradually away its substance, decay is a phenomenon in which the seeds of its own destruction are already implanted in the radioactive chemical element itself. Compared to stable chemical elements, radioactive elements are inherently instable and the varying number of neutrons per nucleus determine the length of the respective half-lives. What is important to note here is that radioactive decay is an internally driven disintegration process, while erosion is set in motion by outside forces.Footnote26

Needless to say, in the institutionalist literature, there is an abundance of definitions of what an institution actually is. These definitions range from very narrow and often formalized understandings to broader conceptions that include informal arrangements as well.Footnote27 Douglass North has proposed one of the most widespread and comprehensive definitions when he famously argued that institutions are “the rules of the game” and the “humanly devised constraints that shape human behavior”.Footnote28 This definition is elastic enough to subsume various strands of institutionalist thinking.Footnote29 For the study of democratic regressions, democratic regimes are usually perceived as a set of intertwined sub-institutions that range from formal institutions like party, electoral or representation systems, to informal ones that are usually unwritten and include diverse institutions like societal norms of for example fairness, forbearance, how to treat the political opposition, to shared behavioural equilibria, and business-government regulations. It is therefore the first and foremost analytical task of scholars to clearly define the borders of the institution or institutional ensemble that they actually study. Based on this decision, the core question in identifying endogenous decay processes is then to what extent the (interplay of sub-) institutions directly generate (unintended and often perverse) incentives, produce inner tensions, or only indirectly enable actions by leaving open regulatory loopholes and not closing gaps that actors can then exploit for subverting this very institution.Footnote30 In contrast, democratic institutions can be washed out by outside forces, marking the opposite pole of erosion processes.

Erosion and decay arguments for democratic regression

This distinction between erosion and decay becomes important when ordering current accounts of democratic regression. I set forth that this major dividing line helps structuring our explanations for the empirical phenomenon of democratic regression.

Unfortunately, social science has already adopted a metaphorical language that does not pay sufficient attention to the analytical difference.Footnote31 For example, the excellent conceptual discussion by Tom Gerald Daly insightfully condenses the current state of the art, but defines decay – like others did for erosion – as the “incremental degradation of the structures and substance of liberal constitutional democracy”, paying less attention to the source of the malaise.Footnote32 At the end of the article, Daly even highlights two prominent research projects, a multi-university consortium “Democratic Erosion” and the “Democratic Decay (Dem-Dec)” project,Footnote33 that are both equally committed to studying democratic regression processes. While these projects share the gradual unfolding of these processes, they do not focus on the question of endogenous or exogenous causation.

Yet, it seems that the erosion metaphor is currently prevailing. In her insightful article, BermeoFootnote34 states for example that “troubled democracies today are more likely to erode rather than to shatter”. GinsburgFootnote35 discusses what needs to be done for an “anti-erosion jurisprudence”, while Lieberman and colleaguesFootnote36 see an “erosion of democratic norms” in the United States. DiamondFootnote37 describes the “significant erosion in electoral fairness, political pluralism, and civic space for opposition and dissent” in Turkey, and the V-Dem scholarsFootnote38 describe recent “democratic erosion processes” in, among others, the Czech Republic, Hungary, Poland, the United States, India, Bulgaria, and Brazil.

Despite the frequent usage of the word, real erosion arguments are rather rare in explaining democratic regression.Footnote39 It might not be too far-fetched to say that its terminological usage is inversely related to actual erosion arguments. One example for exogenous causation is the modification of the idea of “linkage” and “leverage”, originally put forward by Steven Levitsky and Lucan Way.Footnote40 In an attempt to “turn the tables”, the argument runs as follows: the more democratic regimes are linked to autocratic ones, via economic trade, but also communication channels, visits, and cultural affinities of any sort, the stronger the leverage of the autocratic regime to influence and autocratize the democratic regime. While Levitsky and Way have provided ample empirical evidence for the democratization perspective, the autocratization perspective still needs to be tested. As of now, there is no systematic empirical evidence that linkage and leverage actually work also in the other direction. But, beyond doubt, the linkage-leverage-thesis is one that represents the most clear-cut erosion-type of explanation. The autocratic regime is like wind or water the outside force attacking the democratic substance. In Thelen and Streeck’s descriptive terms, democratic institutions can be so displaced, converted, or be layered by active foreign sponsorship. Of course, Russia and China are discussed in this context as the most prominent of these foreign sponsorsFootnote41 or “gravity centers”.Footnote42 Yet, what is important to note here is that in all these processes, the cause is exogenous to the democratic institution that is targeted, marking so a clear-cut erosion process.

While the linkage-leverage hypothesis demands strategic action, this can be relaxed for a related argument. Value-based diffusion can be unintentional.Footnote43 Yet, in parallel to the above, the diffusion of democratic norms is much more researched than the other way around.Footnote44 The current state of the art is still rather cautious about the effect of autocratic diffusion.Footnote45 Future research needs to fill this research lacuna and clarify to what extent an inherent attractiveness of authoritarian values, often catchily coined as the Chinese or Singaporean model,Footnote46 an unintentional diffusion of authoritarian practices, or even the explicit learning from other’s authoritarian exampleFootnote47 explains a deterioration of democratic quality.

Please note that erosion arguments are exogenous arguments, which should not be equated with international arguments. While the linkage-leverage and the diffusion literature focus in their work on international factors, the exogenous force for erosion does not necessarily need to come from the international arena. It can also be bred domestically. The major dividing line is as to whether the cause is generated within or outside the democratic institutions that one studies. To name just a few instances of domestic erosion, an anti-democratic influence of the national military forces, an overly conservative Catholic Church, strong national Islamist traditions, or deep ethno-political cleavages can also constitute domestic exogenous causes.

If taking a historical perspective, exogeneity can also stem from a different angle. If for example the timing, a certain “populist Zeitgeist”,Footnote48 is taken for explanatory purposes and not only as a descriptor of an era in which we live in, it constitutes also rather an exogenous than an endogenous factor for explaining democratic regression. Yet, more empirical research is needed here as well that demonstrates how timing actually develops causal power within domestic democratic regression processes, let alone how contagious it is across countries.Footnote49 Moreover, if we adopt an explanatory perspective in which we treat the past as exogenous to our institutions under study, then today’s democratic regressions can be explained by previous low-quality democratizations. These democratizations suffered particularly from economic and social inequality and weak political structures, providing already a fertile ground for democratic regressions. Adopting such a perspective means to treat this history as an exogenous cause for today’s situation.Footnote50 The causes for today’s deterioration of democratic quality are here generated outside (i.e. temporally prior to) the (current) institutions under study.Footnote51 Take for example the case of the Philippines. It is argued here that the former military dictator Ferdinand Marcos established a system of patronage, corruption, cronyism and wide-spread pork-barrel politics in which political institutions were destroyed or severely weakened.Footnote52 This authoritarian shadow that is still tangible until today continues to erode current democratic substance, both in terms of political culture and government institutions. Hutchcroft and RocamoraFootnote53 aptly summarize that in the post-Marcos era “the logic of patronage remains central to understanding Philippine politics, and political parties remain weak, ill-defined, and poorly institutionalized”.

In turn, rivalling arguments are of endogenous nature. Democratic regression happens often within democratic core institutions that have been initially built to guarantee horizontal and vertical accountability. The arguably most influential work today on this topic, the book on “How Democracies Die” by Steven Levitsky and Daniel Ziblatt,Footnote54 uses the classic and seminal work by Juan LinzFootnote55 which can also be read more in terms of endogenous than exogenous causation. Linz suggested a list of four key indicators. First, Linz spoke about a weak commitment to the democratic “rules of the game”, as evidenced in undermining the legitimacy of elections, taking extraconstitutional means like military involvement in politics or violent insurrections. A second warning signal refers to the denial of the legitimacy of the political opponent and to what extent they are defamed as criminal, subversive, foreign agents or constituting a threat to national security. A third aspect is toleration or even an encouragement of violence by actors close to the incumbent. A final dimension of authoritarian behaviour in democratic politics is the willingness and readiness to restrict civil liberties of political opponents, including press freedom, freedom of movement, and freedom of association. These indicators by Linz can be used to identify countries that are at high risk or that already entered democratic regression. What is important to note here is that these causes are rather generated within than outside the democratic institutions.

Another prominent argument of inner tensions within the institutional design of democracies has lately been put forward by Dan Slater and Aries Arugay.Footnote56 They argue – using Thailand, the Philippines, Indonesia, and Taiwan as empirical examples – that democratic institutions demand vertical accountability and horizontal accountability at the same time, thereby following simultaneously the conflictive aim of inclusion and constraint, causing internal institutional conflict that sparks institutional polarization. In a similar vein, Milan SvolikFootnote57 compellingly demonstrates that the causes for democratic regression “lies in a vulnerability that is inherent to democratic politics.” He develops an argument in which authoritarian populists exploit a dilemma that is ingrained into the democratic institution of elections. Elections provide voters with two choices that can be conflictive, particularly in countries with deep political cleavages and acute tensions: democratic principles on the one hand and partisan interests, embodied by populist leaders, on the other hand. Using experimental methods, SvolikFootnote58 shows for Turkey, Venezuela, and the United States that a significant portion of the population “act as partisans first and democrats only second”, ranking partisan interests higher than democratic principles. Like for the Slater and Arugay study, the cause of democratic regression is seen by Svolik in endogenous tensions rather than in exogenously driven processes.

The relevance of endogenous explanations of democratic regression are bolstered by empirical evidence. SvolikFootnote59 argues that democratic subversions are either caused by military coups or executive turnovers. In his account, between 1973 and 2018 88 of 197 cases of democratic declines have been caused by executive takeovers, while only 46 cases can be attributed to military involvement into civilian politics. The time trend is clear: Since 2005 four out of five democratic regressions are caused by democratically elected incumbents that abuse their power. And one of their most important tools for undermining democracy is – paradoxically – law and the liberal democratic constitution.Footnote60 Kim Lane ScheppeleFootnote61 captivatingly demonstrates in this context how “legalistic autocrats” exploited the inherent tension between a (vulgarized understanding of) democracy and constitutionalism to the detriment of liberal values.

To sum up, erosion arguments, if taken seriously, refer to a cause that is generated outside the institution under study. Despite the high usage of the term, this type of argument seems to be rather rare. Linkage-leverage-arguments arguments are prototypical for such an endeavour. In contrast, decay arguments about democratic regression that focus on endogenous tensions within democratic designs seem to be overall more widespread. This might be open to debate, but the distinction between the locus of the cause should be made. The source of the malaise needs to be located in the first place. This is not only for the sake of analytical clarity but might have also important repercussions on advising political praxis.

Zooming into the causal mechanism of democratic regression

The locating of a cause has direct implications for detecting causal mechanisms. In an admittedly very simplified version, an explanation of a phenomenon includes causes X, a causal mechanism M, and an outcome Y (X → M → Y). In the previous section, I have introduced the major distinction between endogenous and exogenous causes. This section is dedicated to detailing the causal mechanism M. The set of causes X and their inherent properties impact the working of the causal mechanism. Yet, while properties of the cause influence the mechanism, both should be kept separate from each other for analytical purposes.

Let me first clarify my understanding of a causal mechanism. It goes almost without saying that its meaning is hotly contested. In an insightful review article, John GerringFootnote62 lists at least nine different meanings of what a causal mechanism can be. Similarly, James MahoneyFootnote63 lists 24 slightly varying definitions by 21 authors. If there is any common ground between these differing meanings, then I would follow Gerring’s suggestion and see it in a “pathway or process by which an effect is produced”.Footnote64 It seems to be intuitive that a mechanistic explanation focuses on what happens between X and Y. In close analogy to physical mechanics, Hedström and YlikoskiFootnote65 suggest therefore to think of the “cogs and wheels (…) through which the outcome to be explained was brought about”. Taking this analogy further, the idea of disentangling the complex processes of democratic regression is to dissect the bits and pieces in order to see how they interrelate and work together. In analytical terms, this is the task of a clockmaker who opens the clock case in order to see how the cogs and wheels interact.

As a further general caveat in zooming into the study of causal mechanisms, their generative and repeated nature need to be emphasized. Both attributes are highlighted by Renate Mayntz.Footnote66 A causal mechanism should generate the outcome and not remain as a mere concurrent epiphenomenon. While this seems to be less controversial for democratic regression mechanisms, she pays emphasis that a mechanism invokes notions of regularity and should not be limited to idiographic case-specific explanations. For her, a causal mechanism should be, at least in principle, transportable from one specific context to another. A causal mechanism should produce the same outcome when specified initial circumstances are met. The recurrent nature of regression mechanism needs to be empirically demonstrated. This condition might meet more scepticism in the case-oriented literature, but nevertheless remains a useful thought exercise for abstracting from the specific for the sake of the general.Footnote67

Components of a causal mechanism

I follow a substantive understanding of causal mechanisms as complex systems of interlocking and interacting parts. In philosophy of science, a widely used definition of causal mechanism proves to be helpful here. A causal mechanism consists of “entities and activities organized such that they are productive of regular change from start-up to finish or termination of condition”.Footnote68 Activities are understood as the “producer of change” while entities are “the things that engage in activities”.Footnote69 This dualistic understanding and the explicit distinction between activities and entities is crucial here.Footnote70 Moreover, the analytical sociological tradition would add that we also need to look for actor-centered micro-foundations of the macro-relationship.Footnote71 When theorizing processes of democratic regression, explicitly clarifying between (micro-)entities and their related activities of a causal mechanism constitutes an important empirical step.

As argued above, the properties of the cause X do impact the causal mechanism M and the way it is studied. It is straightforward to argue that endogenous or exogenous causation makes us look at different locales. It is like marking a cross on a map that tells us where to dig deeper. When digging deeper into a decay process, the focus of our search for entities and activities lies automatically within the institution under study. Take the example of the autocratic legalism argument that I mentioned above.Footnote72 It is endogenously anchored. When detailing the causal mechanism behind this argument, the place to look for lies in inherent institutional weaknesses and loopholes that make it possible, sometimes even incentivize, formally democratically elected leaders to non-use, ab-use, and/or mis-use existing, but dormant laws to the detriment of liberal democracy. While in the legalism mechanism the “non-, ab- and mis-use” of laws refers so to the concrete activities, the involved entities are the governments that instrumentalize lower-level courts as well as supreme and constitutional courts and reform them in such ways that like-minded judges are appointed, and that critical voices are suppressed, seizing incrementally power over courts, undermining judicial independence in the alleged name of the people, curtailing then the rights of the opposition, and violating subsequently civil liberties and political rights.

Consider the empirical example of South Korea under Lee Myung-bak and Park Geun-hye.Footnote73 It illustrates the inner working of the “autocratic legalism” mechanism that ScheppeleFootnote74 and CorralesFootnote75 showed for Hungary and Venezuela, i.e. the gradual conversion of existing laws for illiberal purposes. Stephen Haggard and Jong-Sung YouFootnote76 argue for example that the South Korean democratic regression lies in the conjunction of several legal tactics by the government. In this context, they refer to the abuse of criminal defamation laws, to abuse of election laws, and the abuse of the National Security Law. Using the language of historical institutionalism, this line of argument can be subsumed under endogenous displacement in which an insurrectionary type of change agents activates “previously suppressed or suspended possibilities”,Footnote77 being enabled by a weak institutional context.Footnote78 Under the presidency of Lee, it is shown that the number of indictments for defamation doubled, often involving massive attacks on the freedom of expression.Footnote79 Also, electoral laws were bended, ranging from illegal use of money and gifts to illegal propaganda, and violations of neutrality orders.Footnote80 While the National Security Law that entails the prohibition of so-called “anti-government organizations” has been in great decline during the liberal governments between 1998 and 2007, it saw a sharp increase when Lee entered office.Footnote81

The South Korean case shares many similarities with the Indonesian democratic regression episode between 2007 and 2014, exhibiting the recurrent nature of the autocratic legalism mechanism. Warburton and AspinallFootnote82 speak aptly of an “illiberal drift”. They argue that not only “draconian laws on defamation and blasphemy”Footnote83 have been used in more instances, but that the Indonesian government also relied on the 2013 Law on Societal Organizations (“NGO Law”) that prohibit, sanction, and censor non-governmental organizations critical of the state doctrine Pancasila. Also like the South Korean example, the Indonesian democratic regression is explained by “electoral narrowing”Footnote84 in which electoral laws have been used by the incumbents to raise the hurdles for competition thresholds, nomination procedures, and financing and campaigning, transforming Indonesian democracy “into a system of intra-incumbency contestation that excluded other forces trying to penetrate it”.Footnote85 These policies can be adequately subsumed under an endogenous causal mechanism of autocratic legalism.

In contrast, when exogenous erosion processes are traced, scholars need to concentrate on external actors outside the institution under study. The research focus should lie then on the strength of the external forces that work from the outside in. As such, erosion arguments seem to be generally more uni-directional, depending largely on the magnitude and intensity of the outside force that gradually weakens democratic substance. In turn, decay arguments are characterized by internal dynamics that often involve self-reinforcing feedback loops. As such, the source of the cause does not only tell us where to search for entities and activities for spelling out the causal mechanism, but also give us hints to probable inner workings, highlighting already implicit temporalities that should be made explicit.

Accounting for temporality in causal mechanisms

Beyond dissecting a causal mechanism into its components and demonstrating its recurrent nature, temporality is a crucial, but often underrated feature of a causal mechanism in general – and of democratic regression mechanisms in particular.Footnote86 While the dissecting into components of a causal mechanism is often at least implicitly done, the temporality question remains underspecified in the current literature. Temporality covers the tempo of a process, as well as its duration, acceleration, sequencing, and timing. In her admirable article, Anna Grzymala-BusseFootnote87 not only clarified the differences between these temporal dimensions, but also gave concrete advice on how to operationalize them and how to methodically approach them.

In most empirical instances, democratic regression is a slow process (tempo) that takes a long time to develop (duration). Usually, democratic regression is – already in its name – a process in which democratic substance is gradually weakened or hollowed out over a longer period of time. While we might agree that these parameters are often shared, they come with considerable empirical complications. Duration covers the temporal length of how long a process operates, necessitating so not only the identification of a clear starting and end point, but also establishing what Grzymala-BusseFootnote88 calls a “temporal baseline”. We do not only need to justify the boundaries of an event or a process, but also how we temporally relate this process to other processes. Do we argue in terms of objective time, measured for example in months or years, or do we relate it to the length of previous episodes? Moreover, what counts as democratic regression, given that this is a complex phenomenon consisting of several temporally overlapping sub-phenomena? Also, how do we deal with phenomena that slowly accumulate over time, remaining under the radar of both academia and praxis, before they finally enter a threshold and become visible? How should we classify these invisible processes?Footnote89

In the introduction to this special issue on democratic regression in Asia-Pacific, Croissant and HaynesFootnote90 propose for example a 10% decline in V-Dem’s Electoral Democracy Index and V-Dem’s Liberal Democracy Index to define a democratic regression. The starting point of the episode is marked by such a drop and is interrupted when either a stagnation is observed over four years or when a substantial increase is observed. This means that Croissant and Haynes use an objective time (years) and do not relate it to the length of previous episodes. Also, it should be noted that the indices that Croissant and Haynes use are situated on a rather high aggregation level in which profound changes have already manifested themselves in the respective countries. This should not be misunderstood as a critique of their approach, but rather as an attempt to make the implicit explicit.

Justifying decisions for delineating the respective regression episodes is not a trivial task that gets even more complicated when we consider tempo. Tempo of democratic regression can be defined as the amount of decline in democratic quality per time period (duration). While tempo (fast and slow) should not be conflated with duration (short and long), it should also be kept separate from arguments about acceleration. Acceleration is change of tempo per time unit, taking into account the nonlinear nature of democratic regression processes. The (unexpected) increase in tempo might not only bring about turbulence, but also fosters situational logics in which the emergence of new actors or the sudden re-shuffling of power asymmetries in actor constellations is catalysed.Footnote91 While it still needs to be systematically tested, a hypothesis could be formulated: Democratic regressions that can be traced back to exogenous erosion remain rather on a constant tempo as the exogenous effect often remains invariant over time. In turn, decay processes are more inclined towards internal dynamics and self-reinforcing feedback loops, suggesting acceleration processes.

Finally, sequencing and timing are two further crucial aspects of causal mechanisms.Footnote92 To my reading, they remain underexplored, but should be on the future research agenda on democratic regression as well. A sequence is nothing more than an “ordered list of elements”.Footnote93 Yet, for crafting convincing causal sequencing arguments about democratic regressions, it needs to be shown that it is the order of events that actually matters. In other words, the burden of proof lies in empirically demonstrating that a sequence of X1 → X2 → X3 leads to the outcome Y, but a sequence of say X1 → X3 → X2 would not. It is the order of events that develops causal power. I am not aware of empirical case studies that focus on this type of explanation. Yet, it seems to be a promising route, particularly for an endogenous type of explanation.

In contrast to sequence arguments, timing does not refer to the relative ordering of events within a sequence, but it is anchored in an exogenous context. For timing arguments, it is the change of the context that matters. It is the temporal circumstances that cause a process. Applied to democratic regressions, the Zeitgeist argument that I mentioned above illustrates this thinking.Footnote94 Yet, again, to my reading of the state of the art, this is an underexplored topic that should be addressed more systematically. While we might all agree that we recently observe a clustering of democratic regressions, it still needs to be shown that the timing does have an independent causal impact on (or at least serve as a catalyst or facilitator for) these phenomena, both being effective within a country and contagious across countries.

To sum up, when zooming into M, the burden of empirical proof lies (a) in demonstrating the generative and (in principle) recurrent nature of the causal mechanisms; (b) in decomposing the causal mechanism into its entities and activities and potentially accounting for micro-level foundations; and (c) in integrating previously underexplored aspects of temporality that range from duration, tempo, and acceleration to issues of timing and sequencing.

Conclusion

This article is written in light of the current rise of democratic regression phenomena. It seeks to classify existing approaches and explanations in a novel way, pledging on the one hand for analytical clarity and synthesizing on the other hand their insights into a “checklist” how we could methodologically approach democratic regressions. While I maintain that democratic regression processes are not only multi-faceted, but also multi-causal, I argue that we should even be more analytically precise and dissect the complex phenomenon into its constitutive parts. Three points are central.

First, I seek to establish a new axis along which we can classify existing accounts. Using historical neo-institutionalism as a theoretical starting point, the crucial dimension is the source where the cause for democratic regression originates. I broadly distinguish between endogenous and exogenous explanations to organize and categorize existing explanatory factors. To illustrate the different logics, I use the natural science metaphors of endogenous decay and exogenous erosion.

Second, I illustrate these considerations with selected secondary literature and empirical cases. As such, I argue that despite the frequent usage of the term “erosion”, decay arguments are not only more widespread, but also more convincing. Exogenous causes that are found in the literature employ often a reversed linkage-leverage argument. In contrast, endogenous causes argue more with inherent institutional tensions, be it between conflictive goals of inclusion and constraint or between democratic and partisan principles.

Third, I argue that it is key for analytical precision to not only distinguish the sources of the cause X, but separate the cause X from the causal mechanism M. I do not question that X and M are interconnected and that properties of X influence the inner working of M. To the contrary, I argue that we should take advantage of this interconnectedness as the source of the cause gives us an orientation where to dig deeper. It is the marking on a map that shows us where to dig deeper. The study of causal mechanism details the concrete pathway by which the cause leads to the outcome, with its preeminent task lying in decomposing its constitutive components, the involved activities and entities, and in accounting for varying temporalities.

While the current state of the art provides ample empirical material for dissecting the mechanisms into its components, the temporal dimension seems to be still underexplored. When systematically detailing the inner workings of a causal mechanism, basal temporal dimensions of duration, tempo and acceleration, but also of timing and sequencing should be made more explicit. They constitute a useful toolbox for refining our causal mechanisms with which we seek to explain democratic regression. Yet, as much as future research could pick up these currently neglected dimensions, it needs to be seen to what extent the classifications that I propose here proves to be helpful guidance in ordering a fuzzy field.

Acknowledgements

The original idea for this paper grew out of a more general project on types of institutional change (Gerschewski 2020). Here, I take up the initial idea of distinguishing between endogenous and exogenous forms of change and spell it out for the realm of democratic regressions. I would like to express my deep gratitude to Aurel Croissant and Jeff Haynes as the editors of Democratization and of this special issue. I thank the participants of the University of Heidelberg’s Workshop on “Democratic Backsliding in Asia” as well as the anonymous reviewers for their constructive feedback and insightful advice. For helpful research assistance, I thank Louisa Böttner.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).

Additional information

Funding

Research for this contribution is part of the Cluster of Excellence “Contestations of the Liberal Script” (EXC 2055, Project-ID: 390715649), funded by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research Foundation).

Notes on contributors

Johannes Gerschewski

Johannes Gerschewski is a Research Fellow at the WZB Berlin Social Science Center and the Academic Coordinator of the Theory Network at the Berlin-based Cluster of Excellence “Contestations of the Liberal Script”. In 2013, he was awarded the “Frank Cass Award for Best Article by a Young Scholar” from the journal Democratization. His articles have appeared in American Political Science Review, Perspectives on Politics, Comparative Political Studies, Democratization, and Government and Opposition. His research interests lie in comparative democratization and democratic as well as autocratic theory, with a particular focus on questions of regime legitimation and research methodology.

Notes

1 There are many ways in which democratic quality can be measured. See among many the edited volume by Diamond and Morlino, Assessing the Quality of Democracy. I would also like to highlight that I use democratic regression as the umbrella term for similar phenomena that have been sometimes called “de-democratization”, “democratic recession”, “democratic backsliding”, or “autocratization”. For an overview of the relevant literature and the differences between the concepts, please refer to Croissant and Haynes, Democratic Regressions in Asia-Pacific.

2 Bermeo, “On Democratic Backsliding”; Diamond, “Facing Up the Democratic Recession”; Waldner and Lust, “Unwelcome Change”.

3 Daly, “Democratic Decay”.

4 Tomini and Wagemann, “Varieties of Contemporary Democratic Breakdown and Regression”.

5 Norris, Democratic Deficit.

6 Waldner and Lust, “Unwelcome Change”.

7 Croissant and Haynes, Democratic Regressions in Asia-Pacific.

8 Mayr, “Cause and Effect in Biology”.

9 In his work on democratic breakdowns, Maeda also distinguishes between endogenous and exogenous termination of democratic rule, the latter being caused by democratically elected incumbents, the latter being caused by forces outside the democratic government. I share with him the emphasis on the source of the cause, but rather look at gradual forms of change instead of breakdowns, and expand the distinction between endogenous and exogenous causes to institutions more generally. See Maeda, “Two Modes of Democratic Breakdown”.

10 Streeck and Thelen, “Introduction”; Mahoney and Thelen, “A Theory of Gradual Institutional Change”.

11 Fioretos, Falleti and Sheingate, The Oxford Handbook of Historical Institutionalism.

12 Immergut, “The Theoretical Core of the New Institutionalism”.

13 Collier and Collier, Shaping the Political Arena; Mahoney, The Legacies of Liberalism.

14 Pierson, “Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics”; Arthur, Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy; Arrow, “Increasing Returns”.

15 Capoccia, “Critical Junctures and Institutional Change”; Capoccia and Kelemen, “The Study of Critical Junctures”; Collier and Munck, “Building Blocks and Methodological Challenges”.

16 Thelen, “Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Politics”; Thelen, How Institutions Evolve; Mahoney and Thelen, “A Theory of Gradual Institutional Change”; Streeck and Thelen, “Introduction”; Slater, “Altering Authoritarianism”; Tsai, “Adaptive Informal Institutions and Endogenous Institutional Change in China”.

17 Soifer, “The Causal Logic of Critical Junctures”.

18 See also from a different perspective Greif and Laitin, “A Theory of Endogenous Institutional Change”; Weyland, “Toward a New Theory of Institutional Change”.

19 For a critical review of Thelen’s argument see also van der Heijden, “A Short History of Studying Incremental Institutional Change”.

20 Streeck and Thelen, Beyond Continuity.

21 Mahoney and Thelen, Explaining Institutional Change. Ambiguity, Agency, and Power.

22 Streeck and Thelen, “Introduction”, 24.

23 Mahoney and Thelen, “A Theory of Gradual Institutional Change”.

24 Ibid.; Streeck and Thelen, “Introduction”; Thelen, How Institutions Evolve; Thelen, “Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Politics”.

25 Streeck and Thelen, “Introduction”, 21.

26 For a more detailed discussion about the distinction between erosion an decay processes as well as other forms of institutional change arguments, see Gerschewski, “Explanations of Institutional Change”.

27 Helmke and Levitsky, “Informal Institutions and Comparative Politics”; Immergut, “The Theoretical Core of the New Institutionalism”; Hall, “Politics as a Process Structured in Space and Time”.

28 North, Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, 3.

29 For some scholars, the wide usage of “institutions” might seem inadequate. Some might prefer concepts like system, structure, field, or regime as a bounded whole. Yet, to make the argument about endogenous and exogenous causation, it suffices to establish a border of what counts as within and what counts as outside of the entity.

30 For example, Maeda skillfully analyses the impact of presidential vs parliamentary systems (the institution) on democratic breakdown. Drawing on the classic debate initiated by Linz in the 1990s, he empirically demonstrates that there must be something within the institution of the presidential system (polarization, winner-takes-all-attitude, deadlock, rigidity, dual legitimacy etc.) that generates perverse incentives so that “presidents in presidential systems are more likely to become authoritarian than prime ministers in parliamentary systems”, Maeda, “Two Modes of Democratic Breakdown”, 1141.

31 A remarkable conceptual discussion can also be found in Sadurski’s recent book on “anti-constitutional populist backsliding” in Poland. Here, Sadurski criticizes the term “decay” for being too passive and actorless, neglecting the enthusiasm and energy that key actors have invested to dismantle the constitutional state. I agree with Sadurski here that decay – as well as erosion – could be understood in this way. Yet, I would like to alleviate these concerns. Moreover, it might be particularly the study of causal mechanisms that re-focuses again on the centrality of actors. See Sadurski, Poland's Constitutional Breakdown, 12–4.

32 Daly, “Democratic Decay”, 17.

33 See their online platforms: www.democratic-erosion.com and www.democratic-decay.org

34 Bermeo, “On Democratic Backsliding”, 14.

35 Ginsburg, “The Jurisprudence of Anti-Erosion”; also in Ginsburg and Huq, How to Save a Constitutional Democracy.

36 Lieberman et al., “The Trump Presidency and American Democracy”, 476.

37 Diamond, “Facing up the Democratic Recession”, 147.

38 Lührmann et al., “State of the World 2018”.

39 Waldner and Lust, “Unwelcome Change”.

40 Levitsky and Way, Competitive Authoritarianism.

41 Diamond, Ill Winds; Bader, China's Foreign Relations and the Survival of Autocracies.

42 Kneuer and Demmelhuber, “Gravity Centres of Authoritarian Rule”.

43 Hanson and Kopstein, “Regime Type and Diffusion in Comparative Politics Methodology”.

44 Mainwaring and Pérez-Liñán, “Lessons from Latin America”.

45 Weyland, “Autocratic Diffusion and Cooperation”; Bank, “The Study of Authoritarian Diffusion and Cooperation”; Buzogány, “Illiberal Democracy in Hungary”.

46 Bell, The China Model.

47 Scheppele provides for example evidence that the “autocratic legalists” learned from each other and borrowed some of their tactics from other autocratic legalists, see Scheppele, “Autocratic Legalism”, 550–6.

48 Mudde, “The Populist Zeitgeist”.

49 Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, “Studying Populism in Comparative Perspective”.

50 Waldner and Lust, “Unwelcome Change”, 101–2.

51 Of course, this analytical distinction is made by the scholar. In contrast, the past can also be endogenized in our explanations of democratic regression. If for example, the autocratic past in the Philippines – with the year 1986 marking a sharp break – is not treated as an independent exogenous factor to explain today’s democratic regression, but if the respective research design takes a longer historical perspective and connects temporally remote periods in order to adequately account for the continuity of a process, the autocratic past is endogenized for explaining today’s regression.

52 Thompson, The Anti-Marcos Struggle; Kang, Crony Capitalism; Overholt, “The Rise and Fall of Ferdinand Marcos”.

53 Hutchcroft and Rocamora, “Strong Demands and Weak Institutions”, 281.

54 Levitsky and Ziblatt, How Democracies Die.

55 Juan J. Linz, “Crisis, Breakdown, and Reequilibration”.

56 Slater and Arugay, “Polarizing Figures”.

57 Svolik, “Polarization versus Democracy”, 23.

58 Ibid., 27.

59 Ibid.

60 Ginsburg and Huq, How to Save a Constitutional Democracy; Corrales, “The Authoritarian Resurgence”; Ebetürk and Över, Insult, Charisma, and Personalization of Power.

61 Scheppele, “Autocratic Legalism”, 557.

62 Gerring, “Review Article: The Mechanismic Worldview”.

63 Mahoney, “Beyond Correlational Analysis”.

64 Gerring, “Review Article: The Mechanismic Worldview, 177.

65 Hedström and Ylikoski, “Causal Mechanisms in the Social Sciences”, 50.

66 Mayntz, “Mechanisms in the Analysis of Social Macro-Phenomena”.

67 Hedström and Swedberg, “Social Mechanisms”; Hedström and Swedberg, Social Mechanisms.

68 Machamer, Darden and Craver, “Thinking about Mechanisms”, 3.

69 Ibid.

70 Rohlfing, Case Studies and Causal Inference, 36.

71 Tilly, “Mechanisms in Political Processes”; Hedström and Swedberg, “Social Mechanisms”.

72 Scheppele, “Autocratic Legalism”; Corrales, “The Authoritarian Resurgence”.

73 Shin and Moon, “South Korea after Impeachment”.

74 Scheppele, “Autocratic Legalism”.

75 Corrales, “The Authoritarian Resurgence”.

76 Haggard and You, “Freedom of Expression in South Korea”.

77 Streeck and Thelen, “Introduction”, 21.

78 Shin, “The Rise and Fall of Park Geun-hye”.

79 Haggard and You, “Freedom of Expression in South Korea”, 169–70.

80 Cho and Kim, “Procedural Justice and Perceived Electoral Integrity”.

81 Haggard and You, “Freedom of Expression in South Korea”, 172.

82 Warburton and Aspinall, “Explaining Indonesia's Democratic Regression”.

83 Ibid., 260.

84 Mietzner, “Authoritarian Innovations in Indonesia”.

85 Ibid., 4.

86 Abbott, Time Matters; Pierson, Politics in Time; Pierson, “Big, Slow-Moving and … Invisible”; Pierson, “Not Just What, but When”.

87 Grzymala-Busse, “Time will Tell?”.

88 Ibid., 1280.

89 Skaaning, “Waves of Autocratization and Democratization”.

90 Croissant and Haynes, Democratic Regressions in Asia-Pacific.

91 Grzymala-Busse, “Time will Tell?”, 1286–9; Volpi and Gerschewski, “Crises and Critical Junctures in Authoritarian Regimes”.

92 Pierson, “Not Just What, but When”; Hanson and Kopstein, “Regime Type and Diffusion in Comparative Politics Methodology”.

93 Abbott, “Sequence Analysis”, 94.

94 Mudde, “The Populist Zeitgeist”.

Bibliography

  • Abbott, Andrew. “Sequence Analysis: New Methods for Old Ideas.” Annual Review of Sociology 21 (1995): 93–113.
  • Abbott, Andrew. Time Matters: On Theory and Methods. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001.
  • Arrow, Kenneth J. “Increasing Returns: Historiographic Issues and Path Dependence.” The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 7, no. 2 (2000): 171–180.
  • Arthur, W. B. Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994.
  • Bader, Julia. China's Foreign Relations and the Survival of Autocracies. London: Routledge, 2015.
  • Bank, André. “The Study of Authoritarian Diffusion and Cooperation: Comparative Lessons on Interests Versus Ideology, Nowadays and in History.” Democratization 12, no. 3 (2017): 1–13.
  • Bell, Daniel A. The China Model: Political Meritocracy and the Limits of Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2015.
  • Bermeo, Nancy. “On Democratic Backsliding.” Journal of Democracy 27, no. 1 (2016): 5–19.
  • Buzogány, Aron. “Illiberal Democracy in Hungary: Authoritarian Diffusion or Domestic Causation?” Democratization 24, no. 7 (2017): 1307–1325.
  • Capoccia, Giovanni. “Critical Junctures and Institutional Change.” In Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis, edited by James Mahoney, and Kathleen Thelen, 147–179. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
  • Capoccia, Giovanni, and Daniel R. Kelemen. “The Study of Critical Junctures: Theory, Narrative and Counterfactuals in Historical Institutionalism.” World Politics 59, no. 3 (2007): 341–369.
  • Cho, Youngho, and Yong C. Kim. “Procedural Justice and Perceived Electoral Integrity: The Case of Korea's 2012 Presidential Election.” Democratization 23, no. 7 (2016): 1180–1197.
  • Collier, Ruth Berins, and David Collier. Shaping the Political Arena: Critical Junctures, the Labor Movement, and Regime Dynamics in Latin America. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1991.
  • Collier, David, and Geraldo L. Munck. “Building Blocks and Methodological Challenges: A Framework for Studying Critical Junctures.” Qualitative & Multi-Method Research 15, no. 1 (2017): 2–9.
  • Corrales, Javier. “The Authoritarian Resurgence: Autocratic Legalism in Venezuela.” Journal of Democracy 26, no. 2 (2015): 37–51.
  • Croissant, Aurel, and Jeffrey Haynes. Democratic Regressions in Asia-Pacific. 2020.
  • Daly, Tom G. “Democratic Decay: Conceptualising an Emerging Research Field.” Hague Journal on the Rule of Law 11, no. 1 (2019): 9–36.
  • Diamond, Larry. “Facing up the Democratic Recession.” Journal of Democracy 26, no. 1 (2015): 141–155.
  • Diamond, Larry. Ill Winds: Saving Democracy from Russian Rage, Chinese Ambition, and American Complacency. New York: Penguin, 2019.
  • Diamond, Larry, and Leonardo Morlino, eds. Assessing the Quality of Democracy. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press, 2005.
  • Ebetürk, Irem, and Defne Över. Insult, Charisma, and Personalization of Power: Reviving a Dormant Law. 2020.
  • Fioretos, Orfeo, Tulia G. Falleti, and Adam Sheingate, eds. The Oxford Handbook of Historical Institutionalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.
  • Gamboa, Laura. “Opposition at the Margins: Strategies Against the Erosion of Democracy in Colombia and Venezuela.” Comparative Politics 49, no. 4 (2017): 457–477.
  • Gerring, John. “Review Article: The Mechanismic Worldview: Thinking Inside the Box.” British Journal of Political Science 38, no. 1 (2008): 161–179.
  • Gerschewski, Johannes. “Explanations of Institutional Change. Reflecting on a ‘Missing Diagonal’.” American Political Science Review (2020): 1–16. doi:10.1017/S0003055420000751.
  • Ginsburg, Tom. “The Jurisprudence of Anti-Erosion.” Drake Law Review 66, no. 4 (2018): 823–853.
  • Ginsburg, Tom, and Aziz Z. Huq. How to Save a Constitutional Democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018.
  • Greif, Avner, and David D. Laitin. “A Theory of Endogenous Institutional Change.” American Political Science Review 98, no. 4 (2004): 633–652.
  • Grzymala-Busse, Anna. “Time Will Tell? Temporality and the Analysis of Causal Mechanisms and Processes.” Comparative Political Studies 44, no. 9 (2011): 1267–1297.
  • Haggard, Stephan, and Jong-Sung You. “Freedom of Expression in South Korea.” Journal of Contemporary Asia 45, no. 1 (2015): 167–179.
  • Hall, Peter A. “Politics as a Process Structured in Space and Time.” In The Oxford Handbook of Historical Institutionalism, edited by Orfeo Fioretos, Tulia G. Falleti, and Adam Sheingate, 31–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.
  • Hanson, Stephen E., and Jeffrey S. Kopstein. “Regime Type and Diffusion in Comparative Politics Methodology.” Canadian Journal of Political Science 38, no. 1 (2005): 69–99.
  • Hedström, Peter, and Richard Swedberg. “Social Mechanisms.” Acta Sociologica 39, no. 3 (1996): 281–308.
  • Hedström, Peter, and Richard Swedberg, eds. Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • Hedström, Peter, and Petri Ylikoski. “Causal Mechanisms in the Social Sciences.” Annual Review of Sociology 36, no. 1 (2010): 49–67.
  • Helmke, Gretchen, and Steven Levitsky. “Informal Institutions and Comparative Politics: A Research Agenda.” Perspectives on Politics 2, no. 4 (2004): 725–740.
  • Hutchcroft, Paul D., and Joel Rocamora. “Strong Demands and Weak Institutions: The Origins and Evolution of the Democratic Deficit in the Philippines.” Journal of East Asian Studies 3, no. 2 (2003): 259–292.
  • Immergut, Ellen M. “The Theoretical Core of the New Institutionalism.” Politics & Society 26, no. 1 (1998): 5–34.
  • Kang, David C. Crony Capitalism: Corruption and Development in South Korea and the Philippines. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
  • Kneuer, Marianne, and Thomas Demmelhuber. “Gravity Centres of Authoritarian Rule: A Conceptual Approach.” Democratization 23, no. 5 (2016): 775–796.
  • Levitsky, Steven, and Lucan Way. Competitive Authoritarianism: Hybrid Regimes After the Cold War. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
  • Levitsky, Steven, and Daniel Ziblatt. How Democracies Die. New York: Penguin, 2018.
  • Lieberman, Robert C., Suzanne Mettler, Thomas B. Pepinsky, Kenneth M. Roberts, and Richard Valelly. “The Trump Presidency and American Democracy: A Historical and Comparative Analysis.” Perspectives on Politics 17, no. 2 (2019): 470–479.
  • Linz, Juan J. The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes. Crisis, Breakdown, and Reequilibration. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978.
  • Linz, Juan J. and Alfred Stepan, eds. The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978.
  • Lührmann, Anna, Sandra Grahn, Richard Morgan, Shreeya Pillai, and Staffan I. Lindberg. “State of the World 2018: Democracy Facing Global Challenges.” Democratization 26, no. 6 (2019): 895–915.
  • Machamer, Peter, Lindley Darden, and Carl F. Craver. “Thinking About Mechanisms.” Philosophy of Science 67, no. 1 (2000): 1–25.
  • Maeda, Ko. “Two Modes of Democratic Breakdown: A Cometing Risks Analysis of Democratic Durability.” The Journal of Politics 72, no. 4 (2010): 1129–1143.
  • Mahoney, James. “Path Dependence in Historical Sociology.” Theory and Society 29 (2000): 507–548.
  • Mahoney, James. “Beyond Correlational Analysis: Recent Innovations in Theory and Method.” Sociological Forum 16, no. 3 (2001): 575–593.
  • Mahoney, James. The Legacies of Liberalism: Path Dependence and Political Regimes in Central America. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001.
  • Mahoney, James, and Dietrich Rueschemeyer, eds. Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
  • Mahoney, James, and Kathleen Thelen. “A Theory of Gradual Institutional Change.” In Explaining Institutional Change. Ambiguity, Agency, and Power, edited by James Mahoney, and Kathleen Thelen, 1–37. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
  • Mahoney, James, and Kathleen Thelen, eds. Explaining Institutional Change. Ambiguity, Agency, and Power. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
  • Mahoney, James, and Kathleen Thelen, eds. Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
  • Mainwaring, Scott, and Fernando Bizzarro. “The Fates of Third-Wave Democracies.” Journal of Democracy 30, no. 1 (2019): 99–113.
  • Mainwaring, Scott, and Aníbal Pérez-Liñán. “Lessons From Latin America: Democratic Breakdown and Survival.” Journal of Democracy 24, no. 2 (2013): 123–137.
  • Mayntz, Renate. “Mechanisms in the Analysis of Social Macro-Phenomena.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34, no. 2 (2004): 237–259.
  • Mayr, Ernst. “Cause and Effect in Biology: Kinds of causes, predictability, and teleology are viewed by a practicing biologist.” Science 134, no. 3489 (1961): 1501–1506.
  • McFaul, Michael. “Choosing Autocracy: Actors, Institutions, and Revolution in the Erosion of Russian Democracy.” Comparative Politics 50, no. 3 (2018): 305–325.
  • Mietzner, Marcus. “Authoritarian Innovations in Indonesia: Electoral Narrowing, Identity Politics and Executive Illiberalism.” Democratization 27, no. 6 (2020): 1021–1036.
  • Mudde, Cas. “The Populist Zeitgeist.” Government and Opposition 39, no. 4 (2004): 541–563.
  • Mudde, Cas, and Cristóbal Rovira Kaltwasser. “Studying Populism in Comparative Perspective: Reflections on the Contemporary and Future Research Agenda.” Comparative Political Studies 51, no. 13 (2018): 1667–1693.
  • Neumann, Franz. “The Decay of German Democracy.” The Political Quarterly 4, no. 4 (1933): 525–543.
  • Norris, Pippa. Democratic Deficit: Critical Citizens Revisited. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
  • North, Douglass C. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
  • Overholt, William H. “The Rise and Fall of Ferdinand Marcos.” Asian Survey 26, no. 11 (1986): 1137–1163.
  • Pierson, Paul. “Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics.” American Political Science Review 94, no. 2 (2000): 251–267.
  • Pierson, Paul. “Not Just What, but When: Timing and Sequence in Political Processes.” Studies in American Political Development 14, no. 1 (2000): 72–92.
  • Pierson, Paul. “Big, Slow-Moving and … Invisible: Macrosocial Processes in the Study of Comparative Politics.” In Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences, edited by James Mahoney, and Dietrich Rueschemeyer, 177–207. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
  • Pierson, Paul. Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004.
  • Rohlfing, Ingo. Case Studies and Causal Inference: An Integrative Framework. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012.
  • Sadurski, Wojciech. Poland's Constitutional Breakdown. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019.
  • Scheppele, Kim L. “Autocratic Legalism.” The University of Chicago Law Review 85, no. 2 (2018): 545–584.
  • Shin, Soon-ok. “The Rise and Fall of Park Geun-hye: The Perils of South Korea’s Weak Party System.” The Pacific Review 33, no. 1 (2020): 153–183.
  • Shin, Gi-Wook, and Rennie J. Moon. “South Korea After Impeachment.” Journal of Democracy 28, no. 4 (2017): 117–131.
  • Skaaning, Svend-Erik. “Waves of Autocratization and Democratization: a Critical Note on Conceptualization and Measurement.” Democratization (2020): 1–10. doi:10.1080/13510347.2020.1799194.
  • Slater, Dan. “Altering Authoritarianism: Institutional Complexity and Autocratic Agency in Indonesia.” In Explaining Institutional Change. Ambiguity, Agency, and Power, edited by James Mahoney, and Kathleen Thelen, 132–167. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
  • Slater, Dan, and Aries A. Arugay. “Polarizing Figures: Executive Power and Institutional Conflict in Asian Democracies.” American Behavioral Scientist 62, no. 1 (2018): 92–106.
  • Soifer, Hillel D. “The Causal Logic of Critical Junctures.” Comparative Political Studies 45, no. 12 (2012): 1572–1597.
  • Streeck, Wolfgang, and Kathleen Thelen, eds. Beyond Continuity: Institutional Change in Advanced Political Economies. New York: Oxford University Press, 2005.
  • Streeck, Wolfgang, and Kathleen Thelen. “Introduction: Institutional Change in Advanced Political Economies.” In Beyond Continuity: Institutional Change in Advanced Political Economies, edited by Wolfgang Streeck, and Kathleen Thelen, 1–39. New York: Oxford University Press, 2005.
  • Svolik, Milan. “Polarization Versus Democracy.” Journal of Democracy 30, no. 3 (2019): 20–32.
  • Thelen, Kathleen. “Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Politics.” Annual Review of Political Science 2 (1999): 369–404.
  • Thelen, Kathleen. How Institutions Evolve: The Political Economy of Skills in Germany, Britain, the United States and Japan. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
  • Thompson, Mark R. The Anti-Marcos Struggle: Personalistic Rule and Democratic Transition in the Philippines. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1995.
  • Tilly, Charles. “Mechanisms in Political Processes.” Annual Review of Political Science 4 (2001): 21–41.
  • Tomini, Luca, and Claudius Wagemann. “Varieties of Contemporary Democratic Breakdown and Regression: A Comparative Analysis.” European Journal of Political Research 57, no. 3 (2018): 687–716.
  • Tsai, Kellee S. “Adaptive Informal Institutions and Endogenous Institutional Change in China.” World Politics 59, no. 1 (2006): 116–141.
  • van der Heijden, Jeroen. “A Short History of Studying Incremental Institutional Change: Does ‘Explaining Institutional Change’ Provide any New Explanations?” Regulation & Governance 4, no. 2 (2010): 230–243.
  • Volpi, Frédéric, and Johannes Gerschewski. “Crises and Critical Junctures in Authoritarian Regimes: Addressing Uprisings’ Temporalities and Discontinuities.” Third World Quarterly (2020): 1–16. doi:10.1080/01436597.2020.1729728.
  • Waldner, David, and Ellen Lust. “Unwelcome Change: Coming to Terms with Democratic Backsliding.” Annual Review of Political Science 21 (2018): 93–113.
  • Warburton, Eve, and Edward Aspinall. “Explaining Indonesia's Democratic Regression: Structure, Agency, and Popular Opinion.” Contemporary Southeast Asia 41, no. 2 (2019): 255–285.
  • Weyland, Kurt. “Toward a New Theory of Institutional Change.” World Politics 60, no. 2 (2008): 281–314.
  • Weyland, Kurt. “Autocratic Diffusion and Cooperation: The Impact of Interests vs. Ideology.” Democratization 76, no. 4 (2017): 1–18.