995
Views
10
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Original Articles

Presentism and Precursorship in Intellectual History

Pages 49-72 | Published online: 15 Apr 2008
 

Abstract

Presentism, which is to say the application of concepts of the present to the study of the past, is a topic that has recently earned a high level of attention, especially in the history of science and in the history of ideas. Over the past few decades, the historiographical discussion of the role that presentism plays has gradually become dominated by anti‐presentist methodologies. This article provides a careful overview of the debate about anti‐presentism in the history of science and the history of ideas; the coverage of the debate especially tries to pay attendance to non‐English language writings. The article argues that these anti‐presentist positions ultimately derive their plausibility from a historical availability principle. A significant part of the article is devoted to the examination of the availability principle, according to which historians should avoid interpretations that use linguistic and epistemic resources unavailable to the authors and their contemporaries. After a thorough reconstruction and critical assessment of the availability principle, I conclude that strict anti‐presentist accounts of historical interpretation ultimately face some major problems due to the implausibility of a general application of the availability principle. Against strict anti‐presentist methodologies I argue that presentisms might play a relevant and legitimate role in some areas of intellectual history.

Acknowledgements

For helpful comments I am especially indebted to Mark Bevir (Berkeley), Aviezer Tucker (Belfast), Adrian Wilson (Leeds) and Ian Hunter (Brisbane).

Notes

1 Four classic texts should be mentioned: Butterfield (Citation1931); Schuyler (Citation1932); Lovejoy (Citation1939); Febvre (Citation1942). The most important narrative experiment in principled anti‐presentism is by Martin Rudwick (Citation1985). The current debate about the role of present‐centred interpretations takes place for the most part under the descriptions of ‘presentism’, ‘anachronism’ and ‘whiggism’. A representative sample of the most important surveys of this debate would certainly include A. Rupert Hall (Citation1969; Citation1983), T. G. Ashplant and Adrian Wilson (Citation1988), Adrian Wilson and T. G. Ashplant (Citation1988), Ernst Mayr (Citation1990), John Pickstone (Citation1995), Nicholas Jardine (Citation2000b; Citation2003) and Malcolm Gaskill (Citation2006).

2 For an eloquent defence of a history of science which deals with the ‘failures’ and ‘losers’ in the history of science, see Robert Merton (Citation1975: 336).

3 For methodological considerations on precursorship in the history of science and intellectual history, compare among others Henri Bergson (Citation1934) (important comments on Bergson’s theory of precursorship are to be found in Danto Citation1985: 168–69; Veyne Citation1996: 423–29), Joseph Clark (Citation1959), I. E. Drabkin (1959), Georges Canguilhem ([Citation1966] Citation1994), Iris Sandler (Citation1979), Helge Kragh (Citation1987: 100–03), Tom Kindt and Hans‐Harald Müller (Citation2000) and Judith Schlanger (Citation2001).

4 These questions have resurfaced in recent years (Boucher Citation1984; Bevir Citation1994; Vanheeswijck Citation2001; D’Oro Citation2004) and tend to be discussed in relation to the problematicist account of Robin George Collingwood (see Collingwood [1939] 1978). Unfortunately, recent discussions ignore the (primarily neo‐Kantian) German tradition of Problemgeschichte which was stated most systematically by Nicolai Hartmann (see Hartmann [Citation1909] 1958; [Citation1936] 1957). A good account of German Problemgeschichte is provided by Michael Hänel (Citation2001).

5 Skinner’s thoughts on an availability principle can be positioned within the methodological programme of the Cambridge School of the history of political ideas. For a critical reconstruction of this programme see David Boucher (Citation1985), Mark Bevir (Citation1999) and Kari Palonen (Citation2003). Jardine’s availability principle is not, like Skinner’s, oriented towards chronological, but rather towards ‘institutional’ variables. While Skinner’s availability principle excludes all interpretations which were inaccessible to the historical author and his contemporaries (Skinner Citation1988), Jardine excludes all interpretations which would have been inaccessible to an idealised ‘competent participant’ or ‘competent practitioner’. According to Jardine, the availability principle requires precisely those interpretations that were available to the competent participants of the ‘form of life’ or the ‘style of inquiry’ to which the historical object to be interpreted belongs (see Jardine Citation2000a: 247–50). Jardine’s term ‘form of life’ is conveyed through Peter Winch’s influential interpretation of this concept in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations (Winch Citation1958: 40–42).

6 The availability principle has an intentional and a modal dimension: the former is not subject to closer analysis in this article. For a brief reconstruction of the intentional dimension, see Adrian Haddock (Citation2002: 7).

7 A variety of criticisms of the availability principle can be found in the contributions by Margot Leslie (Citation1970), David Hull (Citation1979), Christopher Janaway (Citation1988), Gary Hardcastle (Citation1991), Murray McGillivray (Citation1994), Aristides Baltas (Citation1994) and Nick Tosh (Citation2003).

8 See Robert Wachbroit (Citation1987: 45); some objections to the anti‐presentist position take a similar direction, suggesting that due to an institutionalised dislike for success stories, there is reluctance to talk about the central goal of the history of science, namely to provide information about scientific progress (Laudan Citation1990: 56–57).

9 Kuhn blamed the retrospective construction of tradition as produced by textbooks for the ‘invisibility’ of scientific revolutions. He assumes here that the histories written by natural scientists for ‘textbooks’ must have the same goals and functions as the histories written by historians of science. He also assumes therefore that both types of the history of science should be subject to the same evaluative criteria. This assumption has been contested, and with good reason; see Thomas Nickles (Citation1992).

10 Some authors argue against using presentist forms of description in propaedeutics (see Allchin Citation2004).

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 371.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.