1,599
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric

Abstract

In recent years, an old challenge to informed consent has been rediscovered: the challenge of ignorance. Several authors argue that due to the presence of irreducible ignorance in certain treatments, giving informed consent to these treatments is not possible. The present paper examines in what ways ignorance is believed to prevent informed consent and which treatments are affected by that. At this, it becomes clear that if the challenge of ignorance truly holds, it poses a major problem to informed consent. The paper argues, however, that from both an empirical and a theoretical point of view, it is not convincing that ignorance prevents informed consent. Still, it seems important that the presence of irreducible ignorance is openly discussed during the informed consent process.

INTRODUCTION

Informed consent is considered the core principle of bioethics (Eyal Citation2019). It has the power to transform an action that is morally unacceptable to a morally acceptable one (Manson and O’Neill Citation2007; Miller and Wertheimer Citation2010a; Bullock Citation2018). For instance, if a physician injects a patient with a drug or performs surgery on them, it is considered an assault unless the physician has the patient’s valid consent. This is what some have called the moral magic of consent (Alexander Citation1996; Hurd Citation1996).

Historically, obtaining consent has not always been considered a moral obligation of physicians toward their patients. For example, while Plato (Citation2000) says that a freeman doctor will not prescribe a treatment for a fellow freeman until he has first convinced him, the reason for doing so is not a moral one. Instead, it should bring “the patient more and more under his persuasive influences and set him on the road to health” (IV.720). In line with that, there is no indication in Plato’s work that patients are granted a veto given that they are not convinced by their physician’s treatment plan. This notion of the physician-patient relationship is echoed in the Hippocratic Corpus, which mentions beneficence and non-maleficence as guiding values, while remaining silent about consent (Faden and Beauchamp Citation1986; O’Shea Citation2018).

In the last century, the emergence of the principle of informed consent has led to the gradual replacement of a paternalistic understanding of medical choice, such as that defended by Plato, with a more autonomous one: capacitated patients should be empowered to make their own medical decisions, free from coercion and based on understandable, patient-relevant information. Today, the importance of informed consent is widely accepted, while the literature on informed consent continues to debate its precise requirements (see, e.g., Miller and Wertheimer Citation2010b; Müller and Schaber Citation2018; Eyal Citation2019). Discussions address questions such as what information physicians must disclose, to what extent patients must understand the information, what counts as coercion, and when patients are capacitated. Therefore, the typical question is when informed consent is possible for a treatment, but not if.

Contrary to this general position, some authors have argued already decades ago that for certain treatments, informed consent is never possible because these treatments come with too much irreducible ignorance for that (e.g., Dodds and Jones Citation1989).Footnote1 While this argument, which I will call the challenge of ignorance, has long received little attention in the literature, this has changed in the last few years (e.g., Smith and Sisti Citation2021; Peterson et al. Citation2023; Hofmann Citation2023; Jacobs Citation2023). One reason for that is the rise of the topic of transformative experiences in analytic philosophy (Paul Citation2014; Lambert and Schwenkler Citation2020), which provides a suitable framework for the challenge of ignorance. This new literature makes clear that if irreducible ignorance truly prevents informed consent, then the core principle of bioethics is under broad attack. Therefore, clarification is urgently needed as to whether this is really the case. By examining the challenge of ignorance in detail, the present paper provides such clarification. It analyzes how exactly the challenge of ignorance is believed to undermine informed consent, how this connects to the concept of transformative experiences, and which treatments are affected by it. The paper then argues why the challenge of ignorance does not impede informed consent, making both an empirical and a theoretical case for this.

The remainder of the paper is structured as follows: Section 2 discusses the elements of disclosure and understanding within informed consent and what the current debates about these elements are in the literature, revealing a potential blind spot. Section 3 presents the challenge of ignorance. Section 4 examines in which treatments the challenge of ignorance is present. Section 5 analyzes whether the challenge of ignorance really holds.

THE ELEMENTS OF DISCLOSURE AND UNDERSTANDING

Today’s concept of informed consent is often described as being based on five elements (although it is debated whether all five must be present for consent to be valid): capacity, disclosure, understanding, voluntariness, and consent (Beauchamp Citation2010; Ach Citation2018). To set the stage for the rest of this paper, let us briefly examine two of these elements.

Disclosure means that patients must be provided with information that is material to their decision. But what information is considered material? There are three standards in the literature: The reasonable physician standard requires the physician community to determine what information must be disclosed (McKean, Trachsel, and Croarkin Citation2021). The reasonable patient standard requires physicians to disclose all information that would be material to a reasonable patient. Finally, in addition to these objective standards, there is a subjective standard that requires disclosure of all information that is material to the individual patient (Faden and Beauchamp Citation1986; Dranseika, Piasecki, and Waligora Citation2017). While this standard is rather seen as an ideal that might never be perfectly implemented, it requires physicians to try to find out what disclosure information is material for their patients. For example, a disclosure conversation, in which a patient is encouraged to reflect on their beliefs, desires, and values and to ask questions, can be a helpful way to achieve this (Faden and Beauchamp Citation1986). There are still debates on what must be disclosed and which standard is preferrable (e.g., Dranseika, Piasecki, and Waligora Citation2017; Millum and Bromwich Citation2021).

Understanding requires that the patient has not only been provided information but also has at least some understanding of the information. Accordingly, physicians must translate technical medial jargon into a language that is understandable to the layperson. In doing so, it is not necessary for the physician to give a medical lecture with the goal of having the patient understand every single detail. Having relevant beliefs about the nature and consequences of a medical intervention is usually seen as sufficient (cf. Beauchamp Citation2010). In addition, the patient must understand that by giving consent, they authorize the physician to perform the proposed treatment. Current debates involve to what extent disclosed information must be understood in order that giving consent is possible (e.g., Dougherty Citation2020; Millum and Bromwich Citation2021; Rogers and Johnson Citation2021).

More generally, the debates about the elements of informed consent sketched above address the question of what conditions are necessary for informed consent to be possible (and how feasible these conditions are). At this, it seems undisputed that informed consent is generally possible given that conditions are right. For example, a lack of understanding that prevents informed consent can be addressed by explaining the treatment in a more comprehensive and understandable way. Similarly, insufficient disclosure information preventing informed consent can be complemented with additional disclosure information until it is sufficient. As can be seen, the main question in the informed consent literature on these elements is therefore not if informed consent for a treatment is possible, but when. Could this be a blind spot?

THE CHALLENGE OF IGNORANCE

We can find a line of argument in the literature on informed consent that says that for some interventions, informed consent is generally impossible. This is because some interventions are associated with too much irreducible ignorance to allow for informed consent.Footnote2 For decades, this line of argument lived in the shadows of the medical ethics literature. But since Laurie Paul’s (Citation2014) highly influential book Transformative Experience and the many discussions it has sparked in analytic philosophy, the challenge of ignorance to informed consent has become a rediscovered topic (e.g., Smith and Sisti Citation2021; Peterson et al. Citation2023; Hofmann Citation2023; Jacobs Citation2023). What exactly does this challenge entail?

An early version of the challenge of ignorance can be found in Dodds and Jones (Citation1989). The authors discuss the morality of surrogacy contracts, arguing that even if we assume voluntariness, such contracts are morally impermissible because they risk violating the surrogate’s autonomy. The argument is as follows:

How a pregnancy will be experienced, in detail, is unpredictable, given the limitations of our knowledge of human psychology and physiology, so that even if a woman believes that she will have no emotional response to a child she had gestated, and she tries to ensure this, she may not be able to guarantee that she will not come to have a deep emotional attachment to the child. Thus, how can a woman give fully informed consent to part with a child that she will have felt growing and developing inside her, that she will have given form to through her body, before she knows the feelings these experiences will have produced? If bonding has occurred during a pregnancy, those feelings must be taken into account, but they can only be taken into account in retrospect. (9)

This line of argument touches on the two elements of informed consent discussed in the last section: disclosure and understanding. First, it could be argued that a woman misses information material to her decision, namely how she will emotionally respond to giving away the child after surrogacy. The element of disclosure is therefore not met, depriving her of the ability to give informed consent. Second, it could be argued that a woman lacks understanding of surrogacy because her beliefs about the nature and consequences of surrogacy, particularly its emotional impact on her, are insufficient. Consequently, she cannot give informed consent to surrogacy. Which of these arguments that challenge one of the elements of informed consent is/are convincing?

The claim that the element of disclosure cannot be met in the case of surrogacy is unconvincing. As the term “disclosure” indicates, physicians should not withhold information from their patients but disclose it. First and foremost, physicians are therefore failing their patients if they do not disclose the information that they know and that they assume (or should assume) to be material. Second, it could be argued that physicians also invalidate a patient’s informed consent by failing to disclose information of which they are negligently unaware (cf. Taylor Citation2009). Both of these conditions do not necessarily apply to the surrogacy case. We can think of a physician who discloses all available information to a woman interested in surrogacy, including the fact that she cannot foresee the feelings that surrogacy might evoke. Accordingly, the physician is neither withholding information nor negligently failing to disclose information, suggesting that the element of disclosure is met and does not prevent informed consent.

The challenge that surrogacy poses to informed consent must therefore lie in the element of understanding: women cannot give informed consent to surrogacy because they do not have adequate understanding of how undergoing surrogacy will affect them emotionally. This lack of understanding is fundamental, which means that it does not stem from a lack of capacity or insufficient disclosure.Footnote3 Instead, it stems from a lack of personal experience. Only by undergoing surrogacy, a woman gets an understanding of what its emotional consequences are and how they feel like. In turn, being familiar with the emotional consequences of surrogacy is presumed to be necessary to have adequate understanding of it. Thus, in more general terms, the challenge of ignorance to informed consent is that we know too little about the potential outcomes of some interventions to have adequate understanding of them.

To get a better idea of how the challenge of ignorance undermines understanding, it is useful to look at a current hot topic in analytic philosophy: transformative experience. Paul (Citation2014) has established the concept of transformative experience in her eponymous book. In very short, the book presents two main arguments. First, it emphasizes that experiences can lead to both epistemic and personal transformations. An epistemically transformative experience means that we gain knowledge through an experience that is otherwise unattainable (e.g., the sensory phenomenology of the experience). A personally transformative experience refers to an experience that radically changes our point of view, or, to use another term, our core preferences. Given that an experience is both epistemically and personally transformative, Paul calls it a transformative experience. Second, the book argues that decision theory faces a problem when one of the available options involves an experience that is or can be epistemically and/or personally transformative. The reason for this is that only by undergoing the experience, we learn the value of living it, which Paul calls the subjective value: agents derive the subjective value of an experience by performing a mental simulation of it, but this is not possible (at least not reliably) if we have not had the experience or a similar one before.Footnote4 Next, without being able to anticipate the subjective value of the experience, it is not possible to evaluate the overall value of each option and determine the best choice. Finally, the situation is further complicated by the presence of personal transformation, as it can also affect the future values of known outcomes and requires individuals to choose which preferences they want to hold: their current preferences or transformed preferences (whose characteristics are likely unknown).

The most prominent example of a transformative experience in the literature is becoming a parent (e.g., Paul Citation2014; Barnes Citation2015; Paul Citation2015b; Pettigrew Citation2015; Reuter and Messerli Citation2018; Villiger Citation2023). On the one hand, only by becoming a parent you know how it is to be a parent. On the other hand, becoming a parent can radically change your point of view, making things irrelevant you valued before and vice versa. According to Paul, this makes it impossible to reach a rational decision to have a child, as you lack the necessary information to do so.

The step from the example of becoming a parent to the example of surrogacy is a short one. Dodds and Jones (Citation1989) argue that women cannot foresee the feelings that surrogacy evoke but can only know about these feelings in retrospect. This is a perfect example of an epistemically transformative experience because the sensory phenomenology of surrogacy (including the feelings it evokes) can only be known by experiencing it. In line with that, pregnancy has already been described as being epistemically transformative (Woollard Citation2021). In addition, surrogacy may also be personally transformative. Let’s think of a case where, in the beginning, a woman highly values the fact that she makes it possible for a couple to have a child and start a family. The value of doing so compensates for the expected disvalue of relinquishing the baby she gives birth to. But during pregnancy, these values begin to change as she develops an emotional attachment to the baby, leading her to the point where she wants to keep the child. For example, we seem to find such a transformational process in the testimony of Terese McFadden (Citation1988), who writes about her own surrogacy:

[B]y the time my pregnancy had reached near term, I had no way of coping with what I was about to do. I felt so confused about the couple to whom I was handing over my baby. I began to consider alternatives such as another [couple] or normal adoption. What I had realized at this point was that I really wanted to keep my baby myself. (75)

While this change of mind may have been solely due to an epistemic transformation, it is at least possible that it was (also) due to a personal transformation.

As can be seen, the concept of transformative experience provides a suitable framework for the challenge of ignorance to informed consent. Some medical interventions are or can be epistemically and/or personally transformative, which blocks us from assessing their value.Footnote5 Therefore, we cannot gain adequate understanding of these interventions since their consequences are epistemically inaccessible.

WHERE DO WE FIND THE CHALLENGE OF IGNORANCE?

Beside surrogacy, the medical ethics literature contains many other examples of interventions where the challenge of ignorance is explicitly or implicitly present.Footnote6 At the moment, the most prominent one is psychedelic-assisted therapy. Several authors argue that a psychedelic experience can be both epistemically and personally transformative (e.g., Forstmann et al. Citation2020; Letheby Citation2021; Yudkin et al. Citation2022), and some already touched on what implications this might have for informed consent to psychedelic-assisted therapy (e.g., Smith and Sisti Citation2021; Peterson et al. Citation2023). In a recent analysis of the issue, Jacobs (Citation2023) concludes that the transformative nature of psychedelic-assisted therapy renders informed consent impossible due to inadequate understanding.

A recent article by Hofmann (Citation2023) argues that disease itself can be transformative, which has several implications. First, interventions that result in disease, such as the amputation of a limb in cases of body integrity identity disorder (BIID), can be transformative and thereby prevent informed consent. This problem is also present in the case of treatments of which it is known that they can lead to another disease or make the present disease much worse. Second, the transformative nature of disease is relevant in the research context, for example regarding the question whether low-dose controlled infection is sometimes impermissible because unknown risks render informed consent impossible (see Chappell and Singer Citation2020 for such a discussion on COVID-19). This also raises the question whether patients can ever give informed consent to experimental interventions whose risks are not fully known (cf. Bernstein Citation2005).

In her book, Paul (Citation2014) discusses the cases of a having a cochlear implant to treat deafness or undergoing retinal surgery to treat blindness. In the case of both treatments, it is impossible to anticipate how it will be to live with the new sensory ability, making the experience transformative. In turn, this complicates informed consent. Furthermore, Paul’s primary example of a transformative experience, becoming a parent, can also pose a challenge to informed consent in the medical context, namely in the case of in vitro fertilization. If individuals cannot rationally choose to have a child, how can they have adequate understanding of a treatment that, if successful, will result in having a child?

While the challenge of ignorance has been explicitly emphasized in the examples mentioned above, it is sometimes more implicit, hidden behind another phenomenon: post-treatment regret. Post-treatment regret is a potential consequence of undergoing a treatment in the presence of ignorance, resulting in the wish: “If only I had known!” For instance, post-treatment regret plays an important role in the discussion of surrogacy: during the pregnancy, a surrogate may begin to deeply regret her decision, which some take as an indication that she did not have adequate understanding of surrogacy when choosing it (cf. Oakley Citation1992). The same line of argument can be found in the case of other treatments. To give two examples: (1) Several authors emphasize the major ethical problems that regret cases pose to gender confirmation treatment and that it is imperative to try to prevent post-treatment regret (Landén et al. Citation1998; Smith et al. Citation2005; Olsson and Möller Citation2006). Some authors even treat the possibility of post-treatment regrets as a sufficient reason for gender confirmation treatment being impermissible (cf. McQueen Citation2017). One way to argue for this position is to say that individuals considering gender confirmation treatment do not have adequate understanding of its consequences, preventing informed consent. The fact that gender transition is generally seen as a transformative experience (e.g., McKinnon Citation2015; Villiger Citation2021) appears to be in line with this argument. (2) Concerns regarding potential post-treatment regret are also raised when it comes to sterilization requests, particularly for women under 30 who choose to remain childfree (Lawrence et al. Citation2011). The primary worry is that these women might change their minds in the future and desire to have children, leading to considerable regret. In other words, it is argued that young childfree women may not have adequate understanding of the potential consequences of their decision should their desire not to have children change one day. So here, it is not the treatment that is transformative. Rather, it is considered possible that a woman without a desire for children may at some point undergo a personal transformation that results in a reversal of that preference—something she may believe to be impossible at the moment of sterilization.Footnote7

While the list of examples given above is of course not exhaustive, it should become clear that the challenge of ignorance affects various medical interventions. Thus, if irreducible ignorance truly prevents informed consent, the core principle of bioethics is under broad attack.

DOES IGNORANCE REALLY PREVENT INFORMED CONSENT?

I will provide two arguments why the challenge of ignorance does not prevent informed consent: an empirical one and a theoretical one. While the empirical argument will demonstrate that ignorance does not per se make informed consent impossible, the theoretical argument will show that, in general, the challenge of ignorance does not make informed consent impossible. Let’s begin with the empirical argument.

Empirical Argument Against the Challenge of Ignorance

The challenge of ignorance holds that the transformative nature of a treatment builds an epistemic blockade that prevents us from anticipating what it will be like to undergo the treatment. But is this blockade truly insurmountable? Several authors have argued that experiences can to some extent be imagined even if they are transformative (Sharadin Citation2015; Wilkenfeld Citation2016; Cath Citation2019; Ismael Citation2019; Kind Citation2020; Daoust Citation2021; Randell Citation2023). This is because we can make use of experiences’ higher-order properties, which are properties that an experience shares with other experiences. If we have experiential acquaintance with the higher-order properties of a transformative experience due to our previous experiences, this allows us to partly imagine what undergoing the transformative experience will be like (cf. Villiger Citation2021). While the imagined outcome(s) will not perfectly match the actual outcome, it can still enable us to gain adequate understanding of the outcome(s). To take an illustrative example: The vast majority of people with BIID often or occasionally simulate their desired disability (Giummarra et al. Citation2011; Pennisi and Capodici Citation2021). This behavior called “pretending” helps them to come closer to their felt inner body image and to cope with their disease. For instance, those who desire to amputate a leg often tie that leg up and make it seem like it was amputated. In doing so, they learn how they will look like with an amputated leg, how it will be to be dependent on crutches or a wheelchair, how strangers will react to their disability, and so on. While such pretending cannot perfectly imitate what it is like to have a leg amputated, it does seem to give some understanding of it. In turn, this helps to surmount the epistemic blockade associated with the amputation of a leg (cf. Kasten Citation2009; White Citation2014).

But how do we know whether patients can truly have adequate understanding of a transformative treatment? One way is to examine the reasons why patients want to undergo a treatment and see if those reasons turn out to be valid after the treatment. To resume the example of BIID patients: most BIID patients claim that the primary reason they seek surgery is to correct what they perceive to be a discrepancy between their current body and their true self (First Citation2005). Now, a study on 21 people with BIID who underwent successful amputation found that they were very happy with their bodies after the change, (closely) reached their ideal body image, and felt complete with their body (Kasten and Noll Citation2014). The fact that surgery obviously met their expectations supports the assumption that people with BIID can and often do have adequate understanding of amputation treatment.

Another (and somewhat easier) way to examine whether patients can truly have adequate understanding of a treatment may provide an analysis of post-treatment regret. For instance, although there are women who, like McFadden (Citation1988), have second thoughts about their decision to become a surrogate, such cases are rare. Empirical studies on surrogate mothers show that a large majority does not regret surrogacy (Teman Citation2008; Busby and Vun Citation2010; Jadva, Imrie, and Golombok Citation2015). At this, Busby and Vun (Citation2010) conclude that “the lack of regret and distress expressed by women who choose to be surrogates indicates that they make their decisions with informed consent, an understanding of what the surrogacy arrangement requires and a confidence that they can carry through with their initial decision to participate in surrogacy” (73).Footnote8

However, inferring from low post-treatment regret rates that patients had adequate understanding, as Busby and Vun do, comes with a major problem. A low regret rate primarily indicates that people are happy with their decision and not that they had adequate understanding when making the decision. In fact, it is possible that the only reason a person does not regret a treatment is because the treatment itself changed them personally in such a way that they now value its outcome. Put differently, if they had known the treatment’s outcome in advance, they would not have chosen it, but in retrospect, after the personal transformation, they are glad they did. Ultimately, it is also unclear what a “high” regret rate tells us about understanding. For example, in the case of sterilization, we find a regret rate of about 20% for women 30 years of age or younger (Hillis et al. Citation1999; Curtis, Mohllajee, and Peterson Citation2006). Does that mean that these 20% had inadequate understanding before treatment or that this applies to women not older than 30 in general? In addition, regret may not always be indicative for inadequate understanding, as patients may regret a treatment (or the rejection of a treatment) even though they had adequate understanding of it. This can be the case when a decision involved some risk which patients were aware of, but the risk taken did not pay off for them (cf. McQueen Citation2017). Taken together, it is difficult to draw conclusions about the adequacy of patients’ understanding from post-treatment regret rates (in both directions).

An approach that seems to allow a more general analysis on whether patients can truly have adequate understanding of a transformative treatment is as follows: we compare our ability to anticipate the outcomes of transformative treatments with those of non-transformative treatments. While no such study has been conducted so far, there is a study that generally compares transformative and non-transformative experiences with respect to our ability of affective forecasting (Mathony and Messerli Citation2022). The authors find that our affective forecasting abilities are similarly poor for both types of experiences. This seems to indicate that, contrary to Paul’s argument, ignorance caused by an outcome’s transformative nature does not pose a special problem to ordinary reasoners. In turn, this suggests that the challenge of ignorance does not pose a special problem to informed consent for transformative treatments.

However, we must be cautious about this conclusion for three reasons: First, while the feelings that an experience evokes are certainly of great relevance for its subjective value, Paul (Citation2015a) explicitly rejects reducing subjective value to the value of subjective feel. So, affective forecasting neglects aspects considered crucial to subjective value. Second, affective forecasting is blind to the challenges that the personally transformative aspects of experience can pose (i.e., who do I want to be/become?). Third, the findings of Mathony and Messerli show that people are rather poor reasoners in general. So, maybe we often lack adequate understanding of a treatment, regardless of whether the challenge of ignorance is present (cf. Levy Citation2014). However, this does not imply that the challenge of ignorance no longer poses a special problem: while inadequate understanding due to poor reasoning can be corrected, this is not possible when inadequate understanding is due to irreducible ignorance. Therefore, it is still important to distinguish between the two.

To summarize, assessing the adequacy of understanding by means of an empirical approach comes with problems. Still, there are empirical methods that seem to be able to demonstrate that ignorance does not per se impede understanding (cf. the BIID case). But ultimately, of course, the question of whether there is adequate understanding depends on what adequate understanding actually entails. This brings us to the theoretical argument for why the challenge of ignorance does not make informed consent impossible.

Theoretical Argument Against the Challenge of Ignorance

So far, we said that adequate understanding of a medical intervention includes to have relevant beliefs about the nature and consequences of a medical intervention (cf. Beauchamp Citation2010). But what exactly does that mean? Beauchamp specifies that patients’ “understanding need not be complete, because a grasp of the material facts is generally sufficient, but in some cases a person’s lack of awareness of even a single risk or missing fact can deprive him or her of adequate understanding” (68).

If we compare Beauchamp’s position with other positions in the literature, we find that it is roughly in the middle of the spectrum of how demanding the requirements for understanding should be. Millum and Bromwich (Citation2021), for example, are at the less demanding end of the spectrum. They propose minimal requirements for understanding, including that patients giving consent must understand: (1) that they are being asked for consent; (2) how to exercise their right to give or withhold consent; and (3) to what they are being asked to consent. It is important to notice that this excludes the understanding of risks, purpose, and the like as necessary components of the understanding requirement. Instead, regarding the treatment, patients need only understand what normative boundaries are being redrawn by giving consent (i.e., what do I allow the physician to do with me).Footnote9 Contrary to this, Jacobs (Citation2023), for example, is at the more demanding end of the spectrum. He argues that a key aspect of understanding is to enable a value-aligned decision, which to him is roughly the same as a rational decision and thus requires extensive knowledge. It follows that if a rational decision is not possible, then understanding must be inadequate.

Obviously, ignorance becomes more of a challenge the more demanding the requirements for understanding are. For Millum and Bromwich (Citation2021), ignorance does not pose a problem as long as patients understand to what kind of treatment they are giving consent to. So, if their requirements for understanding are correct, the challenge of ignorance is not valid (but many consider them too minimal). In contrast, for Jacobs (Citation2023), ignorance caused by a treatment’s transformative nature poses a big problem to understanding as it blocks rational decision-making (he follows Paul in this regard). How can patients make a value-aligned decision if they do not know the expected values of their options and how their preferences will change? So, if Jacobs is right, the challenge of ignorance is valid. Ultimately, for Beauchamp’s (Citation2010) account, it is prima facie unclear whether the challenge of ignorance prevents adequate understanding. This depends on how we interpret “a grasp of the material facts” and a “lack of awareness of a risk or missing fact.” Taken together, a way to show that the challenge of ignorance is not valid is to find convincing arguments against Jacobs’s (Citation2023) position and for an interpretation of Beauchamp’s (Citation2010) position that allows informed consent despite the presence of irreducible ignorance.

Let’s first analyze Jacobs’s (Citation2023) position that understanding requires the possibility of a value-aligned decision, which is not given for transformative treatments (he uses the example of psychedelic-assisted therapy). We can object this position in two ways: in the presence of ignorance, a value-aligned decision in Jacobs’s sense is (1) still possible or (2) not necessary for adequate understanding. Regarding the former, there are various accounts in the transformative experience literature that show that rational transformative decision-making is possible even if we cannot infer future values under transformed preferences through mental simulation (e.g., Pettigrew Citation2015; Pettigrew Citation2019; Schulz Citation2020; Villiger Citation2021; Villiger Citation2023). Moreover, McQueen (Citation2017) argues that if a treatment leads to a personal transformation, future values under transformed preferences are irrelevant for the decision at hand. Instead, “one should be sure that the treatment is consistent with who one is now” (1060). This is in line with Isaacs (Citation2020) interpretation of decision theory and critique on the discussion of transformative experience. Therefore, it is much contested whether ignorance prevents value-aligned decisions.

But even if we assume that ignorance prevents value-aligned decisions in Jacobs’s sense, it is doubtful that this renders understanding inadequate. If we look at the history of informed consent, we see its function in the gradual overcoming of a paternalistic understanding of medical choice (cf. O’Shea Citation2018). At the center of this development was the right to self-determination and autonomous choice, which requires patients to be adequately informed about treatment options (this has come to be known as the self-determination theory of informed consent; see, e.g., Faden and Beauchamp Citation1986; Beauchamp and Childress Citation2013; Ach Citation2018). So, the role of understanding in informed consent is to reduce the understanding asymmetry of treatment options between physician and patient: it should enable patients to (at least partially) understand the physician’s arguments for and against certain treatment options, so that they can make an informed autonomous decision. First and foremost, understanding is therefore an obligation of physicians toward patients which includes that they do not only disclose but also explain and discuss information, and make sure that patients understood it. Specifically, physicians must ensure that patients have a grasp of the general risks and benefits of a treatment and explore whether there are individualized risks and benefits that need to be understood.Footnote10

Admittedly, understanding should then support patients in making a good decision, which suggests that a function of informed consent is to promote good decision-making (cf. Bromwich and Millum Citation2017; Dickert et al. Citation2017). Thus, physicians also seem to have some obligation to support patients’ decision-making (Millum and Bromwich Citation2021).Footnote11 But the (recommended) decision does not need to be value-aligned in Jacobs’s sense, which requires knowledge about the transformative outcome(s), including one’s transformed self. Even Savulescu (Citation1994), who proposed one of the most demanding concepts of autonomous medical choice, acknowledges that patients can autonomously choose to explore the unknown as long as they have gathered as many facts as possible about the unknown. This implies that there is nothing inherently irrational about choosing an option one unavoidably lacks information about (cf. Savulescu and Momeyer Citation1997). Thus, even if one were to adopt Savulescu’s highly demanding position, giving informed consent under ignorance would still be possible, provided that the presence of irreducible ignorance is openly discussed. Overall, then, we can reject Jacobs’s (Citation2023) account of understanding.

The arguments outlined above also guide us in how to interpret Beauchamp’s (Citation2010) position on understanding in the context of ignorance. Ignorance does not per se prevent “a grasp of the material facts,” since while patients may not have imaginative acquaintance with certain outcomes, they can still grasp that such outcomes are possible (cf. Brock Citation2007). In addition, there is no “lack of awareness of a risk or missing fact,” since such awareness can and should be promoted by the physician when discussing the presence of ignorance with the patient. Therefore, even in the context of transformative treatments, physicians can fulfill their obligation toward patients to establish adequate understanding. Once they have done so, the patient is in a position to give informed consent, and it is then up to the patient to make the final decision and take the risk, or what Jacobs (Citation2023) calls the “leap of faith,” that comes with a transformative treatment. But what about a patient for whom it is important to know how a transformative outcome feels like and/or in what precise way it may change their preferences? Obviously, the physician cannot provide this information to the patient. Yet, it is generally accepted that “ought” implies “can”. Thus, the inability of the physician to disclose certain information due to irreducible ignorance cannot in itself result in a breach of duty. Because of that, the patient can still give informed consent to the transformative treatment.Footnote12

Finally, we can also approach the discussion form the opposite direction: What are the implications of assuming that patients cannot give informed consent to transformative treatments due to a general lack of adequate understanding? Presumably, this would create an obligation for physicians not to perform transformative treatments because of the irreducible ignorance they are associated with. Consequently, informed consent, which is supposed to promote patient autonomy, would ultimately promote a form of “rational paternalism” by prohibiting patients from choosing transformative treatments.

If we leave the self-determination theory of informed consent and look at other theories on the ethical importance of informed consent, we see that the challenge of ignorance is not a problem either. The social benefit theory basically understands informed consent as a safeguard for social benefits such as trust, which is essential for a functioning health care system (O’Neill Citation2002). Because of that, physicians are required to refrain from exerting controlling influence over patients. As the challenge of ignorance has nothing to do with exerting controlling influence over patients, it does not pose a problem to this account. The patient benefit theory of informed consent includes that informed consent is a suitable instrument for promoting patient’s well-being and preventing harm (Wear Citation1998). This is because individuals usually know best what is good for themselves (cf. Mill Citation1993), and patients’ active participation in the medical decision-making process has beneficial effects on the therapeutic process (Ach Citation2018). The challenge of ignorance does not undermine either of these two reasons for informed consent: by disclosing irreducible ignorance, physicians emphasize that they are not in principle in a better position to decide what is in the patient’s best interest, and by discussing such ignorance they let the patient participate in the decision-making process.Footnote13 Finally, while there is not enough space to discuss second-order accounts of the ethical importance of informed consent (e.g., Wertheimer Citation2014; Eyal Citation2015; Eyal Citation2018), here too, there seems to be no reason why the challenge of ignorance should prevent informed consent.

CONCLUSION

The present paper analyzed the challenge of ignorance which gained momentum in the last few years, partly due to the upcoming concept of transformative experiences. The challenge of ignorance holds that for certain treatments it is per se impossible to give informed consent to, as one does not have the required knowledge to do so. The underlying problem is a lack of understanding of the treatments’ consequences. As the paper has shown, the challenge of ignorance applies to a vast range of medical interventions. So, given that it truly holds, it poses a major problem to medical ethics. However, the analysis of its validity revealed that the challenge of ignorance is neither convincing from an empirical perspective nor from a theoretical perspective: there are transformative treatments where most patients get what they expected, suggesting that they can have adequate understanding of them; and theories on the ethical importance of informed consent are compatible with irreducible ignorance. Therefore, given that the presence of ignorance is openly discussed, it does not prevent informed consent.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I would like to thank Peter Schaber and the anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments on previous versions of this paper.

DISCLOSURE STATEMENT

The author reports no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Funding

This study was funded by Schweizerischer Nationalfonds zur Förderung der Wissenschaftlichen Forschung (grant number: 186151).

Notes

1 A different constraint on consent is posed by morally intolerable cases, in which valid consent is sometimes seen as insufficient for morally transformative consent (cf. Bullock Citation2018).

2 I follow the standard view of ignorance in this paper (cf. Zimmermann Citation2008; Le Morvan and Peels Citation2016). In short, this view defines ignorance as the lack or absence of knowledge; being ignorant that p is a failure to know that p. Furthermore, in this paper, irreducible ignorance associated with an intervention implies that the lack of knowledge cannot be reduced (e.g., by gathering more information) except by undergoing the intervention.

3 There is also the argument that informed consent is often invalid due to a lack of capacity or insufficient disclosure. For example, patients frequently suffer from fallibilities of human reasoning (e.g., the impact bias), which cast doubt on whether patients are truly capacitated in their medical decisions even if they pass a decision-making capacity test (cf. Levy Citation2014). Or, in practice, it is simply not feasible to discuss all information about an intervention or research project, which sometimes would also include new information about new research studies, e.g., in biobank research (cf. Hofmann Citation2009; Boyd Citation2015). However, these challenges to informed consent differ from the challenge of ignorance as they are at least theoretically solvable (e.g., by becoming aware of one’s fallacies or by strictly discussing all the information) and do not per se prevent informed consent.

4 This is why transformative decisions are different from decisions that simply involve a lot of uncertainty: It is not that we just do not know which future state of the world will occur, but that we do not know the very characteristics of one or more possible states of the world. Because of that, we are also ignorant of the value they provide.

5 Note that if we follow Paul’s argument, then even a non-negligible probability that an experience will be transformative impedes rational choice, because it already prevents you from evaluating all possible outcomes.

6 There is also a discussion of the moral weight of advance directives for dementia patients (Walsh Citation2020). In short, the argument is that dementia is a transformative experience and, therefore, individuals at the onset of dementia setting up advance directives cannot foresee what their desires and preferences will be in the moderate-late stage of the disease. Consequently, we should reduce our confidence in the moral weight of advance directives for dementia patients. Although this argument also seems to be based on the challenge of ignorance, we will not discuss it further because the present paper is limited to cases where individuals retain their decision-making capacity.

7 It could also be argued that interventions potentially leading to post-treatment regret are impermissible not because of inadequate understanding but because they may result in harm which a physician must prevent due to the principle of non-maleficence. There are two objections to this argument: (1) in the discussed cases, physicians prolong the suffering of patients if they refuse the intervention and thus, produce harm as well (cf. McQueen Citation2017); and (2) refusing the intervention disrespects the patient’s autonomy.

8 As an aside, in the BIID study conducted by Kasten and Noll (Citation2014) mentioned before, none of the participants regretted the surgery. Similarly, for gender confirmation treatment, a recent meta-analysis finds a regret rate of just below 1% (Bustos et al. Citation2021).

9 The main argument of Millum and Bromwich (Citation2021) is to separate disclosure and understanding requirements. While their proposed requirements for disclosure are quite demanding, their proposed requirements for understanding are minimal. Importantly, the challenge of ignorance also separates disclosure and understanding requirements, however, in a different way. While understanding the required disclosure information is not per se necessary for Millum and Bromwich, understanding the required disclosure information is not sufficient in the context of the challenge of ignorance.

10 Note that Bromwich and Millum (2017) would argue here that these understanding requirements are already too demanding.

11 Since it is good for patients to make better decisions, we can also derive this duty from the duty of beneficence which physicians have towards patients (Burt Citation1979; Emanuel and Emanuel Citation1992; Katz Citation2002). It is important to note, however, that physicians do not have an obligation to ensure that patients do make good decisions, but only to promote good decision-making.

12 It might be objected that the paper misses an element of informed consent that is also relevant for the challenge of ignorance: authenticity. There is a long-standing debate about whether informed consent requires decisions to be made consistent with one’s authentic values and desires, meaning values and desires that are truly one’s own. Interestingly, Paul (Citation2014) also emphasizes the importance of authentic decision-making, which, according to her, is only possible if we can mentally simulate the outcomes. If we follow Paul, authentic transformative decisions are therefore not possible. Consequently, if authenticity is a requirement for informed consent, informed consent for transformative treatment seems not possible either. However, authenticity has been largely rejected as an element of informed consent (cf. Faden and Beauchamp Citation1986; Gunderson Citation1990; Nelson et al. Citation2011; Ahlin Citation2018). This is why the present paper has set it aside.

13 It could be argued that within the patient benefit theory, informed consent under ignorance is not possible because it is unclear which option maximizes expected value. However, this misunderstands the function of informed consent under this theory, which is to promote patient benefit. Even if we assume that it is fundamentally unclear which option maximizes expected value, the informed consent process certainly enables the patient to make a more reflected and likely better decision. Accordingly, the function of informed consent is still preserved.

REFERENCES

  • Ach, J. S. 2018. Consent and medical treatment. In The Routledge handbook of the ethics of consent, ed. A. Müller and P. Schaber, 285–296. Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY: Routledge.
  • Ahlin, J. 2018. The impossibility of reliably determining the authenticity of desires: Implications for informed consent. Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy 21 (1):43–50. doi:10.1007/s11019-017-9783-0.
  • Alexander, L. 1996. The moral magic of consent (II). Legal Theory 2 (3):165–174. Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/S1352325200000471.
  • Barnes, E. 2015. What you can expect when you don’t want to be expecting. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (3):775–786. doi:10.1111/phpr.12242.
  • Beauchamp, T. L. 2010. Autonomy and consent. In The ethics of consent: Theory and practice, ed. F. G. Miller and A. Wertheimer, 55–78. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Beauchamp, T. L., and J. F. Childress. 2013. Principles of Biomedical Ethics (7th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bernstein, M. 2005. Fully informed consent is impossible in surgical clinical trials. Canadian Journal of Surgery 48 (4):271–272.
  • Boyd, K. 2015. The impossibility of informed consent? Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (1):44–47. Institute of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2014-102308.
  • Brock, D. W. 2007. Patient competence and surrogate decision-making. In The Blackwell guide to medical ethics, ed. R. Rhodes, L. Francis, and A. Silvers, 128–141. Blackwell philosophy guides 21. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub.
  • Bromwich, D., and J. R. Millum. 2017. Informed consent to HIV cure research. Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (2):108–113. Institute of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-103122.
  • Bullock, E. C. 2018. Valid consent. In The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent, ed. A. Müller and P. Schaber, 85–94. Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY: Routledge.
  • Burt, R. A. 1979. Taking care of strangers: The role of law in doctor-patient relationships. New York: Free Press.
  • Busby, K., and D. Vun. 2010. Revisiting the Handmaid’s tale: Feminist theory meets empirical research on surrogate mothers. Canadian Journal of Family Law 26:13. HeinOnline.
  • Bustos, V. P., S. S. Bustos, A. Mascaro, G. Del Corral, A. J. Forte, P. Ciudad, E. A. Kim, H. N. Langstein, and O. J. Manrique. 2021. Regret after gender-affirmation surgery: A systematic review and meta-analysis of prevalence. Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery. Global Open 9 (3):e3477. doi:10.1097/GOX.0000000000003477.
  • Cath, Y. 2019. Knowing what it is like and testimony. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 (1):105–120. Taylor & Francis. doi:10.1080/00048402.2018.1433697.
  • Chappell, R. Y., and P. Singer. 2020. Pandemic ethics: The case for risky research. Research Ethics 16 (3-4):1–8. doi:10.1177/1747016120931920.
  • Curtis, K. M., A. P. Mohllajee, and H. B. Peterson. 2006. Regret following female sterilization at a young age: A systematic review. Contraception 73 (2):205–210. doi:10.1016/j.contraception.2005.08.006.
  • Daoust, M.-K. 2021. Transformative experiences, rational decisions and shark attacks. Inquiry :1–21. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2021.1953578.
  • Dickert, N. W., N. Eyal, S. F. Goldkind, C. Grady, S. Joffe, B. Lo, F. G. Miller, R. D. Pentz, R. Silbergleit, K. P. Weinfurt, et al. 2017. Reframing consent for clinical research: A function-based approach. The American Journal of Bioethics: Ajob 17 (12):3–11. Taylor & Francis: doi:10.1080/15265161.2017.1388448.
  • Dodds, S., and K. Jones. 1989. Surrogacy and autonomy. Bioethics 3 (1):1–17. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.1989.tb00323.x.
  • Dougherty, T. 2020. Informed consent, disclosure, and understanding. Philosophy & Public Affairs 48 (2):119–150. doi:10.1111/papa.12164.
  • Dranseika, V., J. Piasecki, and M. Waligora. 2017. Relevant information and informed consent in research: In defense of the subjective standard of disclosure. Science and Engineering Ethics 23 (1):215–225. doi:10.1007/s11948-016-9755-4.
  • Emanuel, E. J., and L. L. Emanuel. 1992. Four models of the physician-patient relationship. Jama 267 (16):2221–2226. American Medical Association. doi:10.1001/jama.1992.03480160079038.
  • Eyal, N. 2015. Informed consent to participation in interventional studies: Second-order in a different sense. Journal of Law and the Biosciences 2 (1):123–128. Oxford University Press: doi:10.1093/jlb/lsv001.
  • Eyal, N. 2018. Informed consent. In The Routledge handbook of the ethics of consent, ed. A. Müller and P. Schaber, 272–284. Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY: Routledge.
  • Eyal, N. 2019. Informed consent. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. N. Zalta, Spring 2019. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  • Faden, R. R., and T. L. Beauchamp. 1986. A history and theory of informed consent. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • First, M. B. 2005. Desire for amputation of a limb: Paraphilia, psychosis, or a new type of identity disorder. Psychological Medicine 35 (6):919–928. Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/S0033291704003320.
  • Forstmann, M., D. A. Yudkin, A. M. Prosser, S. M. Heller, and M. J. Crockett. 2020. Transformative experience and social connectedness mediate the mood-enhancing effects of psychedelic use in naturalistic settings. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 117 (5):2338–2346. doi:10.1073/pnas.1918477117.
  • Giummarra, M. J., J. L. Bradshaw, M. E. R. Nicholls, L. M. Hilti, and P. Brugger. 2011. Body integrity identity disorder: Deranged body processing, right fronto-parietal dysfunction, and phenomenological experience of body incongruity. Neuropsychology Review 21 (4):320–333. doi:10.1007/s11065-011-9184-8.
  • Gunderson, M. 1990. Justifying a principle of informed consent: A case study in autonomy-based ethics. Public Affairs Quarterly 4 (3):249–265. JSTOR.
  • Hillis, S. D., P. A. Marchbanks, L. R. Tylor, and H. B. Peterson. 1999. Poststerilization regret: Findings from the United States collaborative review of sterilization. Obstetrics and Gynecology 93 (6):889–895. doi:10.1016/S0029-7844(98)00539-0.
  • Hofmann, B. 2009. Broadening consent–and diluting ethics? Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (2):125–129. doi:10.1136/jme.2008.024851.
  • Hofmann, B. 2023. Undermining autonomy and consent: The transformative experience of disease. Journal of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-108906.
  • Hurd, H. M. 1996. The moral magic of consent. Legal Theory 2 (2):121–146. Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/S1352325200000434.
  • Isaacs, Y. 2020. The problems of transformative experience. Philosophical Studies 177 (4):1065–1084. Springer. doi:10.1007/s11098-018-01235-3.
  • Ismael, J. 2019. Experience, transformation, and imagination. Rivista Internazionale Di Filosofia e Psicologia 10 (3):330–338.
  • Jacobs, E. 2023. Transformative experience and informed consent to psychedelic-assisted psychotherapy. Frontiers in Psychology 14:1108333. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1108333.
  • Jadva, V., S. Imrie, and S. Golombok. 2015. Surrogate mothers 10 years on: A longitudinal study of psychological well-being and relationships with the parents and child. Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 30 (2):373–9. doi:10.1093/humrep/deu339.
  • Kasten, E. 2009. Body Integrity Identity Disorder (BIID): Befragung von Betroffenen und Erklärungsansätze. Fortschritte Der Neurologie-Psychiatrie 77 (1):16–24. Georg Thieme Verlag KG Stuttgart, New York. doi:10.1055/s-0028-1100837.
  • Kasten, E., and S. Noll. 2014. Body Integrity Identity Disorder (BIID): How satisfied are successful wannabes. Psychology and Behavioral Sciences 3 (6):222–232. doi:10.11648/j.pbs.20140306.17.
  • Katz, J. 2002. The silent world of doctor and patient. Baltimore: JHU Press.
  • Kind, A. 2020. What imagination teaches. In Becoming someone new: Essays on transformative experience, choice, and change, ed. E. Lambert and J. Schwenkler, 133–146. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Lambert, E., and J. Schwenkler, ed. 2020. Becoming someone new: Essays on transformative experience, choice, and change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Landén, M., J. Wålinder, G. Hambert, and B. Lundström. 1998. Factors predictive of regret in sex reassignment. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica 97 (4):284–289. Wiley Online Library. doi:10.1111/j.1600-0447.1998.tb10001.x.
  • Lawrence, R. E., K. A. Rasinski, J. D. Yoon, and F. A. Curlin. 2011. Factors influencing physicians’ advice about female sterilization in USA: A national survey. Human Reproduction (Oxford, England) 26 (1):106–111. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/humrep/deq289.
  • Le Morvan, P., and R. Peels. 2016. The nature of ignorance: Two views. In The epistemic dimensions of ignorance, ed. R. Peels and M. Blaauw, 12–32. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Letheby, C. 2021. Philosophy of psychedelics (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/med/9780198843122.001.0001.
  • Levy, N. 2014. Forced to be free? Increasing patient autonomy by constraining it. Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (5):293–300. doi:10.1136/medethics-2011-100207.
  • Manson, N. C., and O. O’Neill. 2007. Rethinking informed consent in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mathony, M., and M. Messerli. 2022. Transformative experiences, cognitive modelling and affective forecasting. Erkenntnis :1–23. doi:10.1007/s10670-022-00523-z.
  • McFadden, T. 1988. Surrogate motherhood – Refusing to relinquish a child. In The baby machine, ed. J. A. Scutt, 71–76. Melbourne: McCullough Publishing.
  • McKean, A. J., M. Trachsel, and P. E. Croarkin. 2021. The ethics for informed consent for psychotherapy. In The Oxford handbook of psychotherapy ethics, ed. M. Trachsel, J. Gaab, N. Biller-Andorno, Ş. Tekin, and J. Z. Sadler, 1st ed., 259–270. Oxford Handbooks in Philosophy and Psychiatry. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • McKinnon, R. 2015. Trans* formative experiences. Res Philosophica 92 (2):419–440. doi:10.11612/resphil.2015.92.2.12.
  • McQueen, P. 2017. The role of regret in medical decision-making. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20 (5):1051–1065. doi:10.1007/s10677-017-9844-8.
  • Mill, J. S. 1993. On liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Miller, F. G., and A. Wertheimer, ed. 2010b. The ethics of consent: Theory and practice. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Miller, F. G., and A. Wertheimer. 2010a. Preface to a theory of consent transactions: Beyond valid consent. In The ethics of consent: Theory and practice, ed. F. G. Miller and A. Wertheimer, 79–106. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Millum, J., and D. Bromwich. 2021. Informed consent: What must be disclosed and what must be understood? The American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):46–58. Taylor & Francis. doi:10.1080/15265161.2020.1863511.
  • Müller, A., and P. Schaber, ed. 2018. The Routledge handbook of the ethics of consent. Routledge handbooks in applied ethics. Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY: Routledge.
  • Nelson, R. M., T. Beauchamp, V. A. Miller, W. Reynolds, R. F. Ittenbach, and M. F. Luce. 2011. The concept of voluntary consent. The American Journal of Bioethics 11 (8):6–16. doi:10.1080/15265161.2011.583318.
  • O’Neill, O. 2002. Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • O’Shea, T. 2018. Historical perspectives in medical ethics. In The Routledge handbook of the ethics of consent, ed. A. Müller and P. Schaber, 261–271. Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY: Routledge.
  • Oakley, J. 1992. Altruistic surrogacy and informed consent. Bioethics 6 (4):269–287. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.1992.tb00206.x.
  • Olsson, S.-E., and A. Möller. 2006. Regret after sex reassignment surgery in a male-to-female transsexual: A long-term follow-up. Archives of Sexual Behavior 35 (4):501–506. Springer. doi:10.1007/s10508-006-9040-8.
  • Paul, L. A. 2014. Transformative experience (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Paul, L. A. 2015a. Transformative choice: Discussion and replies. Res Philosophica 92 (2):473–545. doi:10.11612/resphil.2015.92.2.15.
  • Paul, L. A. 2015b. What you can’t expect when you’re expecting. Res Philosophica 92 (2):149–170. doi:10.11612/resphil.2015.92.2.1.
  • Pennisi, A., and A. Capodici. 2021. Bodies that love themselves and bodies that hate themselves: The role of lived experience in body integrity dysphoria. In Psychopathology and the Mind: What mental disorders can tell us about our minds, 222–252. New York: Routledge.
  • Peterson, A., E. A. Largent, H. F. Lynch, J. Karlawish, and D. Sisti. 2023. Journeying to Ixtlan: Ethics of psychedelic medicine and research for Alzheimer’s disease and related dementias. The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 14 (2):107–123. doi:10.1080/21507740.2022.2148771.
  • Pettigrew, R. 2015. Transformative experience and decision theory. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (3):766–774. doi:10.1111/phpr.12240.
  • Pettigrew, R. 2019. Choosing for changing selves (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198814962.001.0001.
  • Plato. 2000. Laws. Translated by B. Jowett. New York: Prometheus Books.
  • Randell, P. 2023. Familiar transformative experiences. Synthese 202 (2):45. doi:10.1007/s11229-023-04275-3.
  • Reuter, K., and M. Messerli. 2018. Transformative decisions. The Journal of Philosophy 115 (6):313–335. doi:10.5840/jphil2018115620.
  • Rogers, B. R., and L.-M. Johnson. 2021. Informed consent conversations: Neither the beginning nor the end. The American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):76–78. Taylor & Francis. doi:10.1080/15265161.2021.1907481.
  • Savulescu, J. 1994. Rational desires and the limitation of life-sustaining treatment. Bioethics 8 (3):191–222. Wiley Online Library. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.1994.tb00255.x.
  • Savulescu, J., and R. W. Momeyer. 1997. Should informed consent be based on rational beliefs? Journal of Medical Ethics 23 (5):282–288. doi:10.1136/jme.23.5.282.
  • Schulz, M. 2020. Uncertain preferences in rational decision. Inquiry 63 (6):605–627. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2020.1758767.
  • Sharadin, N. 2015. How you can reasonably form expectations when you’re expecting. Research Philosophica 92 (2):441–452. doi:10.11612/resphil.2015.92.2.2.
  • Smith, W. R., and D. Sisti. 2021. Ethics and ego dissolution: The case of psilocybin. Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (12):807–814. Institute of Medical Ethics. doi:10.1136/medethics-2020-106070.
  • Smith, Y. L., S. H. Van Goozen, A. J. Kuiper, and P. T. Cohen-Kettenis. 2005. Sex reassignment: Outcomes and predictors of treatment for adolescent and adult transsexuals. Psychological Medicine 35 (1):89–99. Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/s0033291704002776.
  • Taylor, J. S. 2009. Practical autonomy and bioethics. Routledge annals of bioethics. vol. 6. New York: Routledge.
  • Teman, E. 2008. The social construction of surrogacy research: An anthropological critique of the psychosocial scholarship on surrogate motherhood. Social Science & Medicine (1982) 67 (7):1104–1112. doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2008.05.026.
  • Villiger, D. 2021. A rational route to transformative decisions. Synthese 199 (5-6):14535–14553. Springer. doi:10.1007/s11229-021-03432-w.
  • Villiger, D. 2023. Rational transformative decision-making. Synthese 201 (3):87. doi:10.1007/s11229-023-04075-9.
  • Walsh, E. 2020. Cognitive transformation, dementia, and the moral weight of advance directives. The American Journal of Bioethics 20 (8):54–64. doi:10.1080/15265161.2020.1781955.
  • Wear, S. 1998. Informed consent. Patient autonomy and clinician beneficence within health care (2nd ed.). Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
  • Wertheimer, A. 2014. (Why) should we require consent to participation in research? Journal of Law and the Biosciences 1 (2):137–182. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/jlb/lsu008.
  • White, A. 2014. Body integrity identity disorder beyond amputation: Consent and liberty. HEC Forum: An Interdisciplinary Journal on Hospitals’ Ethical and Legal Issues 26 (3):225–236. doi:10.1007/s10730-014-9246-4.
  • Wilkenfeld, D. A. 2016. Modeling authenticity. Res Philosophica 93 (1):245–268. doi:10.11612/resphil.2016.93.1.14.
  • Woollard, F. 2021. Mother knows best: Pregnancy, applied ethics, and epistemically transformative experiences. Journal of Applied Philosophy 38 (1):155–171. doi:10.1111/japp.12464.
  • Yudkin, D. A., A. M. B. Prosser, S. M. Heller, K. McRae, A. Chakroff, and M. J. Crockett. 2022. Prosocial correlates of transformative experiences at secular multi-day mass gatherings. Nature Communications 13 (1):2600. Nature Publishing Group. doi:10.1038/s41467-022-29600-1.
  • Zimmermann, M. J. 2008. Living with uncertainty: The moral significance of ignorance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.