6
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Original Articles

Emotion and Thought in Hume's Treatise

Pages 53-71 | Published online: 01 Jul 2013

References

  • 1966 . Passion and Value in Hume's Treatise Edinburgh : Edinburgh University Press . On several main points my description of Hume's theory agrees with those presented in Páll S. Árdal, esp. pp. 7–40, and in Anthony Kenny, Action, Emotion and Will (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963), pp. 20–28. Despite this agreement, however, another description of Hume's theory of the emotions is required for two reasons. First, several quite interesting features of Hume's theory of the connections between emotions and thought are not discussed by either Árdal or Kenny, and deserve to be noticed. Some of these are, as I shall argue, suggestive of a theory more adequate than that which Hume actually provides. Second, the most recent discussion of Hume's theory (Paul J. Dietl, “Hume on the Passions,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, [1968], 554–566) is a sustained critique of the kind of interpretation of Hume which Ardal and Kenny develop. To reveal the unacceptability of Dietl's interpretation, however, requires a more detailed examination of Hume's theory than either Ardal or Kenny provide.
  • Selby-Bigge , L. A. , ed. 1964 . A Treatise of Human Nature Oxford : At the Clarendon Press . All page references in parentheses are to David Hume,. Unless otherwise indicated, all italics are Hume's.
  • The passage continues: “When I am angry, I am actually possest with the passion, and in that emotion have no more a reference to any other object, than when I am thirsty, or sick, or more than five foot high” (415). Kenny claims that in this passage “Hume denies very explicitly the intensionality of the passions.” Kenny, p. 25N. It seems to me, however, that though Hume does deny the intentionality of the emotions, as I shall argue later, he does not do so in the passage which Kenny cites. In this passage, as the context makes clear, Hume is claiming not that emotions have no objects (in the contemporary intentionalist's sense) but that they are not appropriately described as either true or false. Indeed, Hume could well be an intentionalist in the contemporary sense, yet insist on the truth of his present point. Further, it is surely not the case that Hume is here denying that emotions have objects in his sense of “object.” Whether Hume's concept of objects is sufficient to reveal the intentionality of the emotions is a question I shall raise in section 3 of this paper.
  • 1968 . Hume's Intentions London : Gerald Duckworth and Co. . In Hume's sense of “simplicity” an impression can be simple yet resemble other impressions. For a discussion of the tenability of this doctrine see John Passmore, pp. 108f., and Ardal, pp. 12f.
  • Treatise The case of pity causes Hume to modify this condition in an interesting way. See p. 381.
  • These thoughts, as we shall see, are thoughts of what Hume calls the “objects” of the emotions.
  • Treatise It is significant that, in defending his interpretation of Hume's theory of the emotions, Dietl rejects the appropriateness of applying this typically Humean doctrine, defended in Book I of the to the theory of Book II. It is significant, too, that he attempts to play down the associationist, and thus empirical, character of Hume's account of the emotions. Dietl, pp. 563, 566.
  • Wittgenstein , Ludwig . 1963 . Philosophical Investigations Oxford : Basil Blackwell . trans. G. E. M. Anscombe p. 476.
  • Dietl . for one, asserts that Hume is committed to the intentionality of the emotions. Dietl, p. 564.
  • 13 – 14 . In effect I shall argue that one must distinguish two quite independent lines of criticism of a theory of emotions like Hume's, one having to do with privacy, the other with intentionality. The failure to make this distinction imports important confusions into the discussion. Kenny seems subject to these confusions in his comments on Descartes' theory of the emotions. See Kenny, pp.
  • 1968 . Myself and Others 99 – 100 . Oxford : At the Clarendon Press . For an extended discussion of this point see Don Locke, chapter 5, esp. pp.
  • Geach , Peter . 1957 . Mental Acts 3 – 4 . London : Routledge and Kegan Paul .
  • Gardiner , Patrick . 1966 . “Hume's Theory of the Passions,” in ” . In David Hume: A Symposium Edited by: Pears , D. F. 40 London : Macmillan .
  • Though Hume is primarily concerned to make an empirical investigation of the several emotions, and pays little attention to the analysis of the language of the emotions, he is clearly committed to the view that there is correlation between the ordinary English names of the several emotions, and the occurrence of the appropriate sui generis impressions. Thus: “as these words, pride humility, are of general use, and the impressions they represent the most common of any, every one, of himself, will be able to form a just idea of them, without any danger of mistake” (277). One may justifiably, then, make against Hume the kind of objections which I am presently making.
  • 1949 . The Concept of Mind 104 – 105 . London : Hutchison . This point is similar to one made by Gilbert Ryle in pp.
  • Gosling , Compare J. C. 1965 . “Emotion and Object,” . The Philosophical Review , 74 : 503
  • Hume , David . “A Dissertation on the Passions,” . In Essays, Literary, Moral, and Political (London: Ward, Lock and Co., n.d.), p. 389.
  • As noted earlier, p. 54f., it is Hume's view that the pleasantness or painfulness of emotions explains the role which reference to them plays in the explanation of human actions. This holds whether the emotion is, in Hume's words, “calm” or “violent.” Here it is tempting to suggest that the “violence” of an emotion is a matter of the sensations that accompany it. It is not the occurrence of these sensations which explains the behaviour resulting from the emotion, but the pleasantness or painfulness of the emotion itself. Compare Hume's contrast between the “violence” and the “strength” of an emotion (418).

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.