112
Views
15
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Original Articles

“Kilimanjaro”

Pages 141-163 | Published online: 01 Jul 2013

References

  • Much of the line of reasoning presented here was developed during long conversations I enjoyed with Brian McLaughlin, discussions which resulted in a joint paper, ‘Distinctions Without a Difference,’ Southern Journal of Philosophy, 33, supplement (1995) 203–51. I would also like to thank Catherine Elgin and Ralph Wedgwood for helpful discussions.
  • 1994 . London and New York: Routledge
  • Even if you think that all vagueness is either linguistic or mental in origin, you can still make sense of the claim that Kilimanjaro is a vague object, by understanding ‘vague object’ in a derivative sense: A vague object is one that is, considering the purposes that are likely to arise in practice, especially apt to be named by a vague term. This derivative sense is not what we shall have in mind when we discuss the thesis that Kilimanjaro is a vague object. Instead, the thesis will be that the vagueness of Kilimanjaro is part of what the mountain is, independent of human language and thought.
  • In principle, one might hold that ‘Kilimanjaro’ suffers from both kinds of indeterminacy: It is a vague term whose reference is indeterminate among a number of vague objects. It is doubtful that anyone will find such a Baroque position attractive, however, since the principal motive for postulating vague objects is to avoid (as much a possible) the difficulties that come with vague singular terms.
  • Zadeh , Lofti . 1975 . ‘Fuzzy Logic and Approximate Reasoning,’ . Synthese , 30 : 407 – 28 . See
  • 1960 . Word and Object 26 – 68 . Cambridge , Ma : MIT Press . ch. 2, and Ontological Relativity' in Ontological Relativity and Other Essays (New York: Columbia University Press 1969)
  • 1978 . Analysis , 38 : 208
  • Salmon , Nathan . 1981 . Reference and Essence Princeton : Princeton University Press . , 243–45) uses the same formal argument (discovered independently of Evans) as a demonstration of the conclusion that identity is not a vague relation. There is a misstep in Salmon's argument. Having assumed ‘a = b’ as a premiss for reductio ad absurdum, Salmon characterizes ‘a = b’ as “an assumption— something we are taking to be determinately the case for the sake of argument” (244n). But assuming a statement for the sake of a reductio or conditional proof is not at all the same as assuming that that statement is determinately true. Indeed, if assumptions we made for the sake of conditional proofs could be presumed to be determinately true, we could prove outright that no statement is indeterminate in truth value, as follows:
  • |(assumption)
  • ‘φ’ is determinately true (assumptions are determinately true)
  • φ → ‘φ’ is determinately true) (conditional proof)
  • | ∼φ (assumption)
  • | ‘∼φ’ is determinately true (assumption are determinately true)
  • |∼φ' is determinately true) (conditional proof)
  • (∼φ → ‘∼φ’ is determinately true (from 3 and 6 by truth/functional logic)
  • 1991 . A useful and careful investigation of the logic of Evans's argument can be found in Richard Heck's ‘That There Might Be Vague Objects (So Far As Concerns Logic),’ which is part of his MIT Ph.D. thesis.
  • Another worry about existential generalization comes from the fact that, in natural languages, there are denotationless proper names. This worry is less serious, since it can be soothed by adopting the premiss, ‘Kilimanjaro exists,’ then proceeding in free logic.
  • 1966 . Journal of Philosophy , 63 : 128 – 30 . Supervaluations were invented by Bas van Fraassen, ‘Singular Terms, Truth Value Gaps, and Free Logic,’ 464–95. Their application to problems of vagueness is due to Kit Fine, ‘Vagueness, Truth, and Logic,’ Synthese 30 (1975) 265–300. Their application to Evans's specific argument about vague identity statements is due to David Lewis, ‘Vague Identity: Evans Misunderstood,’ Analysis 48 (1988)
  • 21 In van Fraassen's original terminology, for each acceptable Lf-model the function that assigns to each sentence its truth value in 21 is called a classical valuation, while the function that assigns the value true to those sentences true in every acceptable U-model is called a supervaluation.
  • 1996 . Journal of Philosophy , 93 If I read them correctly, Jerry Fodor and Ernest Lepore (‘What Cannot Be Evaluated Cannot Be Evaluated, and It Cannot Be Supervalued Either,’ 516–35) and Timothy Williamson (op. cit., §5.7) have succumbed to this misunderstanding.
  • Chang , C. C. and Keisler , H. J. 1990 . Model Theory, , 3rd ed. North-Holland : Amsterdam . See §2.2.
  • 1974 . Philosophical Review , 83 : 200 – 28 . Details aside, this was the program announced by Hartry Field in ‘Quine and the Correspondence Theory,’
  • To precisely specify a referent for ‘Kilimanjaro,’ we have to determine not only what its parts are, but what its parts would have been if the comet Kohoutek had crashed on its summit; for this purpose, we have to look at worlds other than our own.
  • 1986 . On the Plurality of Worlds 8 – 13 . Cambridge , Ma : Blackwell . (Oxford and, 211–3. See also Quine, Theories and Things (Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard 1981)
  • Lewis . op. cit., 212

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.