127
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Continuity of Theory Structure: A Conceptual Spaces Approach

ORCID Icon &

References

  • Andreas, H., and F. Zenker. 2014. “Basic Concepts of Structuralism.” Erkenntnis 79: 1367–1372. doi: 10.1007/s10670-013-9572-y
  • Balzer, W., C. U. Moulines, and J. D. Sneed. 1987. An Architectonic for Science: The Structuralist Program. Dordrecht: Reidel.
  • Balzer, W., C. U. Moulines, and J. D. Sneed, eds. 2000. Structuralist Knowledge Representation: Paradigmatic Examples. Amsterdam: Rodopi.
  • Born, M. 1953. “Physical Reality.” Philosophical Quarterly 3: 139–149. doi: 10.2307/2216882
  • Campbell, N. R. 1920. Physics: The Elements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Carroll, J. W. 2010. “Laws of Nature.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition), edited by E. N. Zalta. Accessed 11 July 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/laws-of-nature.
  • Chakravartty, A. 2004. “Structuralism as a Form of Scientific Realism.” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 18: 151–171. doi: 10.1080/0269859042000296503
  • Chang, H. 2004. Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Falkenburg, B. 2012. “From Waves to Particle Tracks and Quantum Probabilities.” In From Ultra Rays to Astroparticles, edited by B. Falkenburg and W. Rhode, 265–295. Dordrecht: Springer.
  • French, S. 2014. The Structure of the World: Metaphysics and Representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Friedman, M. 2001. Dynamics of Reason. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
  • Friedman, M. 2002. “Kant, Kuhn, and the Rationality of Science.” Philosophy of Science 69: 171–190. doi: 10.1086/341048
  • Gärdenfors, P. 2000. Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Gärdenfors, P. 2014. The Geometry of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Gärdenfors, P., and A. Stephens. Forthcoming. “ Induction and Knowledge-what.”
  • Gärdenfors, P., and F. Zenker. 2011. “Using Conceptual Spaces to Model the Dynamics of Empirical Theories.” In Philosophy of Science Meets Belief Revision Theory, edited by E. J. Olsson and S. Enqvist, 137–153. Berlin: Springer.
  • Gärdenfors, P., and F. Zenker. 2013. “Theory Change as Dimensional Change: Conceptual Spaces Applied to the Dynamics of Empirical Theories.” Synthese 190: 1039–1058. doi: 10.1007/s11229-011-0060-0
  • Goodman, N. 1983. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. 4th ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Hatfield, G. 2006. “Kant on the Perception of Space (and Time).” In Kant and Modern Philosophy, edited by P. Guyer, 61–93. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Jammer, M. 1960. Concepts of Space: The History of Theories of Space in Physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Kosso, P. 1989. Observability and Observation in Physical Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Krantz, D. H., R. D. Luce, P. Suppes, and A. Tversky. 1971–1990. Foundations of Measurement. 3 vols. New York: Academic Press.
  • Kuhn, T. S. [1962] 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Kuhn, T. S. 1987. “What Are Scientific Revolutions?” In The Probabilistic Revolution, edited by L. Krüger, L. J. Daston, and M. Heidelberger, vol. 1, 7–22. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Kuhn, T. S. 2000. The Road Since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, edited by J. Conant and J. Haughland. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Ladyman, J. 2014. “Structural Realism.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), edited by E. N. Zalta. Accessed 11 July 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/structural-realism.
  • Ladyman, J., and D. Ross. 2007. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Lakatos, I. 1978. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Larvor, B. 2003. “Why Did Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions Cause a Fuss?” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 34: 369–390. doi: 10.1016/S0039-3681(03)00023-2
  • Lindsay, R. B. 1971. “The Concept of Energy and Its Early Historical Development.” Foundations of Physics 1: 383–393. doi: 10.1007/BF00708586
  • Luce, R. D., and P. Suppes. 2002. “Representational Measurement Theory.” In Stevens’ Handbook of Experimental Psychology: Methodology in Experimental Psychology. 3rd ed., edited by H. Pashler and J. T. Wixted, vol. 4, 1–41. New York: Wiley.
  • Masterton, G., F. Zenker, and P. Gärdenfors. 2017. “Using Conceptual Spaces to Exhibit Continuity Through Scientific Theory Change.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 7: 127–150. doi: 10.1007/s13194-016-0149-x
  • Michelson, A. A., and E. W. Morley. 1887. “On the Relative Motion of the Earth and of the Luminiferous Ether.” Sidereal Messenger 6: 306–310.
  • Moulines, C. U. 2014. “Intertheoretical Relations and the Dynamics of Science.” Erkenntnis 79: 1505–1519. doi: 10.1007/s10670-013-9580-y
  • Petersen, G., and F. Zenker. 2014. “From Euler to Navier–Stokes: A Spatial Analysis of Conceptual Changes in Nineteenth-Century Fluid Dynamics.” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 28: 235–253. doi: 10.1080/02698595.2014.953341
  • Poincaré, H. [1908] 1952. Science and Method. Translated by F. Maitland. Mineola, NY: Dover.
  • Post, H. 1971. “Correspondence, Invariance, and Heuristics: In Praise of Conservative Induction.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 2: 213–255. doi: 10.1016/0039-3681(71)90042-2
  • Psillos, S. 1995. “Is Structural Realism the Best of Both Worlds?” Dialectica 49: 15–46. doi: 10.1111/j.1746-8361.1995.tb00113.x
  • Reichenbach, H. [1920] 1965. The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge. Translated by M. Reichenbach. Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Sneed, J. D. 1971. The Logical Structure of Mathematical Physics. Dordrecht: Reidel.
  • Stanford, P. K. 2003a. “No Refuge for Realism: Selective Confirmation and the History of Science.” Philosophy of Science 70: 913–925. doi: 10.1086/377377
  • Stanford, P. K. 2003b. “Pyrrhic Victories for Scientific Realism.” Journal of Philosophy 100: 551–572.
  • Stegmüller, W. 1976. The Structure and Dynamics of Theories. Berlin: Springer.
  • Stevens, S. S. 1946. “On the Theory of Scales of Measurement.” Science 103: 677–680. doi: 10.1126/science.103.2684.677
  • Suppes, P. 2002. Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
  • Tal, E. 2012. “The Epistemology of Measurement: A Model-based Account.” PhD thesis, University of Toronto.
  • Tal, E. 2015. “Measurement in Science.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), edited by E. N. Zalta. Accessed 11 July 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/measurement-science.
  • Thomson, J. J. 1881. “On the Electric and Magnetic Effects Produced by the Motion of Electrified Bodies.” Philosophical Magazine Series 5 11: 229–249. doi: 10.1080/14786448108627008
  • Thomson, J. J. 1897. “Cathode Rays.” Philosophical Magazine Series 5 44: 293–316. doi: 10.1080/14786449708621070
  • Thomson, J. J. 1899. “On the Masses of the Ions in Gases at Low Pressures.” Philosophical Magazine Series 5 48: 547–567. doi: 10.1080/14786449908621447
  • Turney, P. 1990. “Embeddability, Syntax, and Semantics in Accounts of Scientific Theories.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 19: 429–451. doi: 10.1007/BF00263319
  • van Fraassen, B. C. 2008. Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Worrall, J. 1989. “Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds?” Dialectica 43: 99–124. doi: 10.1111/j.1746-8361.1989.tb00933.x
  • Zenker, F. 2014. “From Features via Frames to Spaces: Modeling Scientific Conceptual Change Without Incommensurability or Aprioricity.” In Frames and Concept Types: Applications in Language and Philosophy, edited by T. Gamerschlag, D. Gerland, R. Osswald, and W. Petersen, 69–89. Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Zenker, F., and P. Gärdenfors. 2014. “Modeling Diachronic Changes in Structuralism and in Conceptual Spaces.” Erkenntnis 79: 1547–1561. doi: 10.1007/s10670-013-9582-9
  • Zenker, F., and P. Gärdenfors. 2015. “Communication, Rationality, and Conceptual Changes in Scientific Theories.” In Applications of Conceptual Spaces: The Case for Geometric Knowledge Representation, edited by F. Zenker and P. Gärdenfors, 259–277. Dordrecht: Springer.

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.