92
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Research Article

A Pragmatic-Semiotic Defence of Bivalence

ORCID Icon
Pages 143-157 | Received 07 Mar 2020, Accepted 28 Apr 2021, Published online: 07 Jun 2021
 

Abstract

Since Peirce defined the first operators for three-valued logic, it is usually assumed that he rejected the principle of bivalence. However, I argue that, because bivalence is a principle, the strategy used by Peirce to defend logical principles can be used to defend bivalence. Construing logic as the study of substitutions of equivalent representations, Peirce showed that some patterns of substitution get realized in the very act of questioning them. While I recognize that we can devise non-classical notations, I argue that, when we make claims about those notations, we inevitably get saddled with bivalent commitments. I present several simple inferences to show this. The argument that results from those examples is ‘pragmatic’, because the inevitability of the principle is revealed in use (not mention); and it is ‘semiotic’, because this revelation happens in the use of signs.

Acknowledgements

I want to thank Emily Beattie, Francesco Bellucci, Jeffrey Brian Downard, David Gilbert, Diana Heney, Travis LaCroix, Robert Lane, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Chris Stephens, audience members at the meetings of the Charles S. Peirce Society and the Canadian Philosophical Association, students in my Advanced Formal Logic course, as well as anonymous reviewers for this journal.

Notes

1 Brady Citation2000.

2 Peirce Citation2019; Peirce Citation2020; and more volumes forthcoming.

3 Church Citation1956, 25fn67; Peirce 1931-58, vol. 3, para. 365, hereafter cited as CP 3.365.

4 Anellis Citation2012.

5 Fisch and Turquette Citation1966, 73–5.

6 Lane Citation1998, 1–2.

7 Quine Citation1986, 84.

8 Priest Citation1995b, 5.

9 Priest Citation1995b.

10 Van Benthem et al. Citation2006.

11 Haack Citation1996.

12 Suszko Citation1975.

13 Priest Citation2007.

14 CP 5.250.

15 CP 5.253; see Champagne Citation2009.

16 Bellucci Citation2017, 16.

17 Bellucci Citation2017.

18 Pietarinen and Bellucci Citation2016.

19 Bellucci Citation2017, 42.

20 Hausman Citation2002.

21 Champagne and Pietarinen Citation2020.

22 Bellucci Citation2016, 255; Bellucci Citation2017, 25.

23 CP 2.623.

24 Margolis Citation1998.

25 Like Peirce, I will express rules as conditionals and cases as antecedents of such conditionals.

26 CP 2.466.

27 Bellucci Citation2017, 26.

28 Carroll Citation1895, 279; see Zhang Citation2017, 2.

29 Dutilh Novaes Citation2015.

30 Champagne Citation2016.

31 Legg Citation2012, 13; emphasis in original.

32 Peirce Citation1976, 4, 175; emphasis in original.

33 Peirce Citation1976, 4, 175–6; emphasis in original.

34 Peirce Citation1976, 4, 47–8.

35 Pietarinen Citation2006, 77–102; Hintikka Citation2007.

36 Champagne Citation2015c.

37 Hull and Atkins Citation2017; Legg and Franklin Citation2017.

38 Hitchcock Citation2003, 70–1.

39 Braver Citation2012, 169.

40 Braver Citation2012.

41 Peirce Citation1976, 4, 48.

42 Thomson Citation2011, 24.

43 Cellucci Citation2009.

44 Gentzen Citation1969, 78.

45 Dennett Citation1991.

46 Benacerraf Citation1973.

47 CP 5.253.

48 Sayward Citation1989.

49 CP 5.448; emphasis in original.

50 Priest Citation1995a.

51 Lane Citation1998, 51.

52 CP 2.647.

53 Stjernfelt Citation2014.

54 CP 5.447.

55 Rumfitt Citation2015, 3.

56 CP 1.172.

57 Vargas and Moore Citation2021.

58 Peirce Citation1976, 3, 851; emphasis in original. Quoted in Lane Citation1999, 290.

59 Lane Citation1998, 208.

60 Fisch and Turquette Citation1966, 79.

61 Roberts Citation1973, 64–86.

62 Ma and Pietarinen Citation2018, 3642.

63 Peirce Citation2020, 448; emphasis added.

64 Hintikka Citation1962.

65 Pietarinen Citation2019.

66 Peirce Citation2020, 450.

67 Dummett Citation1959, 149–50. Note that semantic paradoxes do not have to pose the level of worry often attributed to them. See, for instance, the Peirce-inspired argument developed by Prior Citation1976, 141.

68 Legg Citation2014.

69 Raatikainen Citation2004, 133.

70 Howat Citation2013, 453–5.

71 Misak Citation2004, 157; Lane Citation2018, 181.

72 CP 5.265.

74 Pietarinen Citation2020, 135–6; emphasis in original.

75 CP 5.265.

76 Dummett Citation1978, 291–2; Haack Citation1976.

77 Cf. the modus morons of Haack Citation1996, 186–7.

78 CP 2.204.

79 CP 1.623.

80 Howat Citation2014, 482; see Champagne Citation2015a.

81 Brandom Citation1994.

82 Bellucci Citation2017, 43.

83 Manuscript R339; reproduced in Fisch and Turquette Citation1966, 75.

84 CP 5.402.

85 Béziau Citation2012, 251.

86 Manuscript R637, 30; quoted in Bellucci Citation2017, 354.

87 Bellucci Citation2017, 354.

88 CP 5.253.

89 CP 5.397; see Champagne Citation2014.

90 Champagne Citation2015b.

91 Short Citation2007, 288.

92 Thomson Citation2011, 23.

93 Howat Citation2014.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 490.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.