734
Views
7
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Main Articles

Aristotle on the Non-Cause Fallacy

Pages 9-32 | Received 15 Aug 2015, Accepted 16 Aug 2015, Published online: 08 Oct 2015
 

Abstract

When in classical formal logic the notions of deduction, valid inference and logical consequence are defined, causal language plays no role. The founder of western logic, Aristotle, identified ‘non-cause’, or ‘positing as cause what is not a cause’, as a logical fallacy (NCF). I argue that a systematic re-examination of Aristotle's analysis of NCF, and the related language of logical causality, in the Sophistical Refutations, Topics, Analytics and Rhetoric, helps us to understand his conception of (‘syllogism’). It reveals that Aristotle's syllogismhood is non-monotonic, and thus narrower than classical validity as consisting in, or coextensive with, necessary truth-preservation. It also supports the conclusion that a syllogism is a form of relevant consequence: the premisses must be causes of the conclusion in the sense that they are not only sufficient but also necessary for the conclusion to follow. Close analysis of NCF also suggests that syllogistic relevance is not a semantic matter, but a syntactic one: all premisses must be used in the chain of syllogistic deduction leading to the conclusion. Aristotelian syllogistic cannot therefore be accommodated within the framework of classical consequence—as its first interpretations ‘from a modern standpoint’ in the first half of the twentieth century attempted to do.

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to audiences in Groningen, Oxford and Cagliari, and especially to David Charles, Paolo Crivelli, Paolo Fait, Pieter Sjoerd Hasper, Francesco Paoli and an anonymous referee, for their comments on earlier drafts of this article. The preparation of the article was facilitated by the generous support of the Leverhulme Trust, who awarded me a Fellowship for the period January 2014–March 2015.

Notes

1Compare, for example, Smith Citation1997, pp. xi–xxxiv; Slomkowski Citation1997, ch. 1.

2On the issue of the best translation for (‘syllogism’ vs. ‘deduction’), cf., for example, Barnes Citation1981; Mignucci Citation2002; Striker Citation2009, pp. 78–9.

3Adapting the distinction between ‘ostensive’ and ‘through (to) the impossible’ syllogisms of APr. (cf., e.g. 2.14, 62b29–32).

5Compare, for example, Gobbo Citation1997b, p. 342; contra Schreiber 2003, p. 217: ‘Aristotle nowhere in S.E. restricts Non-Cause fallacies to reductio arguments’.

6Compare, for example, Hamblin Citation1970, p. 89, 206. On this interpretation, the non-cause fallacy would be related to the well-known question of how the Socratic elenchus can reveal not only the inconsistency of the premisses, but more precisely the falsehood of one of them.

7For the point that and are two of the species of the genus of ‘opposites’ ( ) cf. Cat. 10, 11b17–23.

8Sometimes this is also referred to simply as , ‘what is posed’, or as ), ‘what was at the beginning’ (from which our ‘begging the question’ jargon: cf. Castagnoli Citation2012).

9For an interpretation along these lines, cf., for example, Sorio Citation2009.

10Compare Smith Citation1989, p. 117.

11Contra Hasper's (Citation2012) translation ‘secures in addition’ and Woods and Hansen Citation2001, p. 403.

12This raises interesting questions, which I cannot explore here, concerning the criteria of identification of ‘arguments’ within the context of dialectical practice.

13The passage is misinterpreted by Woods and Irvine Citation2004, p. 90: ‘In other places, Aristotle suggests a less technical interpretation of the fallacy, in which the trouble with R would simply be its falsity’.

14Compare Smith Citation1989, pp. 141–2.

15On arguments through the impossible cf. also APr. 1.44, 50a29–32; 1.29, 44; 2.11–14; APo. 1.26; Top. 8.14. On these arguments, and arguments ‘from a hypothesis’ more generally, cf. Crivelli Citation2011.

16For in-depth analysis of SE 6 and its relevant context, cf. Gobbo Citation1997a and Malink Citation2014.

17For the ‘compositional use’ of , cf. Fait Citation2004.

18Most manuscripts do not read ; it is debatable whether the phrase is a later addition on the basis of Topics 1.1 (see T7 below). In the absence of there would not be anything equivalent to the clause in the SE version of the definition of (see below).

19This is interesting from the point of view of a developmental study of the parts of the Organon, which I cannot undertake here. Brunschwig Citation2007, p. 293 claims that the fact that NCF in the Topics (see Section 2 below) refers to the Analytics definition of is a piece of evidence for the claim that Topics 8 was written after the Analytics, which were written, in turn, after Topics 1.

20Other translations include: ‘because these things are so’ (Smith Citation1989; Striker Citation2009); ‘du fait que celles-là sont’ (Crubellier Citation2014); ‘par le fait que ces choses sont<le cas>’ (Brunschwig Citation2007); ‘in virtue of the fact that these are the case’ (Frede Citation1974); ‘by their being the case’ (Barnes Citation1980); ‘in virtue of the fact that they are there’ (Mignucci Citation2002).

21For this well-known Aristotelian tenet, cf., for example, APo. 1.2, 71b17–22; 1.13, 78b11–13.

22Schreiber Citation2003, p. 107 confounds the concept of causation operative in the definition of syllogism and in NCF and that operative in the Aristotelian conception of demonstrative syllogism: ‘What Aristotle means by calling the premises “causes” (aitiai) of the conclusion is that the state of the world signified by the premises explains the state of the world signified by the conclusion’ (cf. also p. 112).

23Compare, for example, Charlton Citation1992, p. 100.

24For discussion of this difficult passage, cf., for example, Ross Citation1949, pp. 638–42; Dancy Citation1978, pp. 373–7; Barnes Citation1993, pp. 226–7; Wehrle Citation2000, pp. 8–11; Mignucci Citation2007, pp. 278–80.

25The shift from the premisses to the terms used in them might be due to the fact that in ‘non-perfect’ or ‘incomplete’ syllogisms some transformations of the premisses, and thus additional propositions, are needed, at least to make the necessity evident—but these propositions will include the same terms.

26Compare, for example, Lear Citation1980; Mignucci Citation2002, p. 249; Woods and Irvine Citation2004.

27Compare, for example, Fait Citation2007, p. 129. We will see in Section 3 that Aristotle uses +accusative in his discussion of NCF in the Analytics. For an occurrence of +accusative in SE with reference to NCF see 8, 170a1–2, where Aristotle claims that a type of apparent refutation occurs when, in a reductio ad impossibile, the conclusion ‘does not follow because of the argument’ ( ). I take this to be compatible with the interpretation according to which what does not follow because of the full set of premisses (the logos) is the impossible conclusion.

28Notice that some Greek (and Aristotelian) usages of +genitive have causal force (cf., e.g. Metaph. H3, 1043b8–10: ‘if the threshold is characterised by its position, the position is not produced by ( ) the threshold, but rather the latter by ( ) the former’). Compare also the use of to express material causation in T9 above. For the different view that Aristotle distinguishes ‘necessitation-from’ and ‘necessitation because-of’, cf. Woods Citation2014, p. 111.

29For Aristotle's general statement of the difference between (following by) necessity and syllogism cf. APr. 1.32, 47a31–40.

30The non-monotonicity at play here is not that invoked in systems adopting some form of defeasible consequence, in which the addition of new relevant information can determine that the original defeasible inference is falsified.

31Alexander proposes exactly the same analysis for as a clause barring redundancy in his commentary on the Topics (cf. in Top. 13.25–14.2; 568.18–23).

32Compare, for example, McCall Citation1967; Smiley Citation1973, pp. 139–40; Frede Citation1974, p. 116; Barnes Citation1980, p. 172; Thom Citation1981, pp. 27–31; Cavini Citation1989 and Citation1991, p. 30; Woods and Hansen Citation2001; Mignucci Citation2002; Woods and Irvine Citation2004; Woods Citation2014. For Smiley's and Thom's approach to relevance in Aristotle see p. 19 below.

33There is no in-depth discussion, or sometimes even mention, of this not only in Ross’ (Citation1949) annotated edition, but also in Mignucci's (Citation1969), Smith's (Citation1989), Striker's (Citation2009) and Crubellier's (Citation2014) comments on Aristotle's definition of syllogism in their annotated translations of the Prior Analytics. Smith Citation2011 is agnostic on the issue.

34For introductions to ‘relevant’ (or ‘relevance’) logics, cf., for example, Read Citation1988 and Dunn and Restall Citation2000. On the tension between different criteria of relevance, cf. Paoli Citation2007. One further complication is that most relevant logicians define logical consequence classically (and monotonically), although their systems include non-monotonic implication (I owe this point to Francesco Paoli; cf. Paoli 2007, p. 557).

35The causa apparentiae, to adopt the medieval distinction, as opposed to the causa defectus or non existentiae.

36Compare Fait Citation2007, p. 134: ‘considerare trascurabili o non decisive certe distinzioni che non necessariamente sfuggono all'attenzione’.

37For an analogous point, cf. Gobbo Citation1997a, pp. 240–1.

38Compare, for example, Pickard-Cambridge in Barnes Citation1984 (‘the addition’); Dorion Citation1995 (‘cette addition’); Fait Citation2007 (‘quella cosa [sc. the thing added]’); Hasper Citation2012 (‘it [sc. the thing added]’).

39Compare SE 2, 165a38–b11.

40For a similar suggestion cf. Schreiber Citation2003, p. 110: ‘in this highly condensed text, when the answerer is instructed to “say that he granted it not because it seemed true, but for the sake of argument,” Aristotle is now referring to the premise that truly does cause the impossibility’. For a different interpretation, cf. Sorio Citation2009.

41My proposal would require detailed comparison between reductio ad impossibile refutations and two of the alternative, non-refutative goals that according to Aristotle a questioner might pursue in dialectical exchanges, i.e. leading the interlocutor to something ‘paradoxical’ ( ) or to something false ( ) (cf. SE 3, 12, 17, 176a25–33; Cavini Citation1989; Gobbo Citation1997b). I can only mention here that Aristotle explains that those two goals can be pursued especially in dialectical exchanges in which either there is no set thesis of the answerer at all, or, even if there is one, the questioner asks many questions on subjects not relevant to that thesis (cf. SE 12).

42As Herminius noted, they are listed in decreasing order of gravity (cf. Alex.Aphr. in Top. 567.8–569.8). For a useful analysis of the passage see Smith Citation1997, pp. 141–3.

43 Contra Smith Citation1997, p. 36: ‘Surely that that on which the argument rests makes us overlook the cause.’

45Compare Smith Citation1997, p. 146.

46Compare Smith Citation1989, p. 146.

47In Top. 8.1, 155b20-8, within a discussion of how to secure the premisses for one's argument, it is suggested that some premisses be asked just ‘to give bulk to the argument’ or ‘to conceal the conclusion’. This need not make the resulting argument non-syllogistic, by NCF, provided that its proponent does not pretend to be using these extra premisses when drawing the conclusion.

48Aristotle refers to the Topics, but the reference is most probably to the SE passage T1.

49According to Smith (Citation1989, p. 211), the passage is ‘reminiscent of the efforts of modern relevance logicians to find a formal criterion (such as variable-sharing) for relevance’. Mignucci (Citation1969, p. 678) over-generalises the implications of the examples used in T17: to avoid NCF the conclusion of the reductio must contain either the predicate or the subject term of the hypothesis. But this cannot be correct: the argument ‘All As are B, all Bs are C, all Cs are D, therefore all As are D (impossible)’ can be used as a genuine reductio of the hypothesis ‘All Bs are C’.

50According to Smiley, given ‘the principle that the premisses of a syllogism must form a chain of predications linking the terms of the conclusion’, an Aristotelian syllogism must ‘exclude irrelevant premisses’ (Citation1973, pp. 139–40). Compare also Smiley 1994, p. 30: ‘Aristotle’ case for the chain condition is redolent of relevance—the need for some overt connection of meaning between premises and conclusion as a prerequisite for deduction’. For a similar approach to Aristotelian relevance, cf. Thom Citation1981, pp. 27–31.

51Notice, however, that in A4** another premiss is also eliminated and replaced: (1**) (C is K) is used in place of (1).

52This exegetical puzzle is analogous to the one raised by Aristotle's discussion of begging the question in SE/Topics and in the Analytics (cf. Castagnoli Citation2012).

53Compare Duncombe Citation2014.

54Compare Barnes Citation1980.

55It is difficult to find a reading of the three clauses , and that does not make at least two of them overlap. Some editors have suggested that should be expunged as an intrusive gloss of . For this definition, and Aristotelian enthymemes, cf. Burnyeat Citation1994.

56Compare, for example, Plut. Per. 36 (on Protagoras) and Gorg. Hel. and Pal.

57For a different take on Aristotle on the ‘necessity of saying’, cf. Fait Citation2004.

58Notice that the dialectical language (‘asking’) is no longer presupposing a live dialectical context here, but clearly attests to the dialectical origin of Aristotle's logical reflection.

59For a dismissive analysis of the passage and its value see Barnes Citation1993, pp. 129–30.

60For this approach, cf., for example, Boger Citation2004.

Log in via your institution

Log in to Taylor & Francis Online

PDF download + Online access

  • 48 hours access to article PDF & online version
  • Article PDF can be downloaded
  • Article PDF can be printed
USD 53.00 Add to cart

Issue Purchase

  • 30 days online access to complete issue
  • Article PDFs can be downloaded
  • Article PDFs can be printed
USD 490.00 Add to cart

* Local tax will be added as applicable

Related Research

People also read lists articles that other readers of this article have read.

Recommended articles lists articles that we recommend and is powered by our AI driven recommendation engine.

Cited by lists all citing articles based on Crossref citations.
Articles with the Crossref icon will open in a new tab.