Publication Cover
Inquiry
An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy
Latest Articles
222
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Research Article

Perspectival content of visual experiences

Received 07 Dec 2022, Accepted 04 May 2023, Published online: 22 May 2023

References

  • Alsmith, A. J. T. 2017. “Perspectival Structure and Agentive Self-Location.” In The Subject’s Matter: Self-Consciousness and the Body, edited by F. de Vignemont, and A. J. T. Alsmith, 263–287. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Alsmith, A. J. T. 2021. “The Structure of Egocentric Space.” In The World at Our Fingertips, edited by F. de Vignemont, A. Serino, H. Y. Wong, and A. Farné, 231–250. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bayne, T. 2009. “Perception and the Reach of Phenomenal Content.” The Philosophical Quarterly 59 (236): 385–404. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9213.2009.631.x.
  • Bennett, D. J. 2012. “Seeing Shape: Shape Appearances and Shape Constancy.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63 (3): 487–518. doi:10.1093/bjps/axr018.
  • Bermúdez, J. L. 1998. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Block, N. 2014. “Seeing-as in the Light of Vision Science.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (1): 560–572. doi:10.1111/phpr.12135.
  • Brewer, B. 1992. “Self-location and Agency.” Mind; A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy 101: 17–34. doi:10.1093/mind/101.401.17.
  • Briscoe, R. E. 2009. “Egocentric Spatial Representation in Action and Perception.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (2): 423–460. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2009.00284.x.
  • Briscoe, R. E. 2017. “Multisensory Processing and Perceptual Consciousness: Part II.” Philosophy Compass 12 (12): e12423. doi:10.1111/phc3.12423.
  • Briscoe, R. E. 2021. “Bodily Awareness and Novel Multisensory Features.” Synthese 198 (Suppl 17): S3913–S3941. doi:10.1007/s11229-019-02156-2.
  • Brogaard, B. 2010. “Strong Representationalism and Centered Content.” Philosophical Studies 151: 373–392. doi:10.1007/s11098-009-9437-z.
  • Brogaard, B. 2011. “Are There Unconscious Perceptual Processes?” Consciousness and Cognition 20: 449–463. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.10.002.
  • Campbell, J. 1994. Past, Space and Self. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Carruthers, G. 2008. “Types of Body Representation and the Sense of Embodiment.” Consciousness and Cognition 17: 1302–1316. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2008.02.001.
  • Cassam, Q. 1994. Self and World. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Chomansky, B. 2018. “On the Relation Between Visualized Space and Perceived Space.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 9: 567–583. doi:10.1007/s13164-017-0380-1.
  • Cutter, B., and M. Tye. 2011. “Tracking Representationalism and the Painfulness of Pain.” Philosophical Issues 21 (1): 90–109. doi:10.1111/j.1533-6077.2011.00199.x.
  • de Vignemont, F. 2010. “Body Schema and Body Image—Pros and Cons.” Neuropsychologia 48: 669–680. doi:10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2009.09.022.
  • de Vignemont, F. 2014. “A Multimodal Conception of Bodily Awareness.” Mind; A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy 123 (492): 889–1020. doi:10.1093/mind/fzu089.
  • de Vignemont, F. 2020. “What Phenomenal Contrast for Bodily Ownership?” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 6 (1): 117–137. doi:10.1017/apa.2019.34.
  • Elder, A. 2013. “Proprioception, Anosognosia, and the Richness of Conscious Experience.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (3-4): 83–101.
  • Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Gallese, V. 2007. “The “Conscious” Dorsal Stream: Embodied Simulation and Its Role in Space and Action Conscious Awareness.” PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research on Consciousness 13 (1): 1–20.
  • Gibson, J. J. 1986. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum & Associates.
  • Green, E. J. 2016. “Representationalism and Perceptual Organization.” Philosophical Topics 44 (2): 121–148. doi:10.5840/philtopics201644220.
  • Green, E. J., and S. Schellenberg. 2017. “Spatial Perception: The Perspectival Aspect of Perception.” Philosophy Compass 13 (2): e12472. doi:10.1111/phc3.12472.
  • Gregory, D. 2013. Showing, Sensing, and Seeming. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Harris, L., M. Jenkin, and D. C. Zikovitz. 2000. “Visual and non-Visual Cues in the Perception of Linear Self Motion.” Experimental Brain Research 135: 12–21. doi:10.1007/s002210000504.
  • Hochstetter, G. 2016. “Attention in Bodily Awareness.” Synthese 193 (12): 3819–3842. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1141-x.
  • Jagnow, R. 2012. “Representationalism and the Perspectival Character of Perceptual Experience.” Philosophical Studies 157: 227–249. doi:10.1007/s11098-010-9634-9.
  • Kelly, S. D. 2008. “Content and Constancy: Phenomenology, Psychology, and the Content of Perception.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (3): 682–690. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2008.00164.x.
  • Kinsbourne, M. 1995. “Awareness of One’s Own Body: An Attentional Theory of its Nature, Development, and Brain Basis.” In The Body and the Self, edited by J. L. Bermudez, T. Marcel, and N. Eilan, 205–224. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Kozuch, B. 2015. “Dislocation, not Dissociation: The Neuroanatomical Argument Against Visual Experience Driving Motor Action.” Mind & Language 30 (5): 572–602. doi:10.1111/mila.12091.
  • Kubovy, M., and M. Schutz. 2010. “Audio-visual Objects.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1: 41–61. doi:10.1007/s13164-009-0004-5.
  • Lana, K. 2018. “The Missing Pieces in the Scientific Study of Bodily Awareness.” Philosophical Psychology 30 (5): 571–593. doi:10.1080/09515089.2017.1311999.
  • Lappe, M., F. Bremmer, and A. V. van den Berg. 1999. “Perception of Self-Motion from Visual Flow.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 3 (9): 329–336. doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(99)01364-9.
  • Longo, M. R. 2010. “Implicit and Explicit Body Representations.” European Psychologist 20 (1): 6–15. doi:10.1027/1016-9040/a000198.
  • Longo, M. R., and P. Haggard. 2010. “An Implicit Body Representation Underlying Human Position Sense.” PNAS 107 (26): 11727–11732. doi:10.1073/pnas.1003483107.
  • Longo, M. R., S. S. Rajapakse, A. J. T. Alsmith, and E. R. Ferre. 2020. “Shared Contributions of the Head and Torso to Spatial Reference Frames Across Spatial Judgments.” Cognition 204: 104349. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104349.
  • Longo, M. R., F. Schüuür, M. P. M. Kammers, M. Tsakiris, and P. Haggard. 2008. “What is Embodiment? A Psychometric Approach.” Cognition 107: 978–998. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2007.12.004.
  • Macpherson, F. 2011. “Cross-modal Experiences.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111: 429–468. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9264.2011.00317.x.
  • Marcel, A. 2003. “The Sense of Agency: Awareness and Ownership of Action.” In Agency and Self-Awareness: Issues in Philosophy and Psychology, edited by J. Roessler, and N. Eilan, 48–93. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Mitchell, J. 2021. “Self-locating Content in Visual Experience and the ‘Here-Replacement’ Account.” Journal of Philosophy 118 (4): 188–213. doi:10.5840/jphil2021118414.
  • Noë, A. 2004. Action in Perception. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
  • O’Callaghan, C. 2015. “Not all Perceptual Experience is Modality Specific.” In Perception and its Modalities, edited by D. Stokes, M. Matthen, and S. Biggs, 133–165. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • O’Callaghan, C. 2017. “Grades of Multisensory Awareness.” Mind & Language 32 (2): 155–181. doi:10.1111/mila.12137.
  • Peacocke, C. 1992. A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Peacocke, C. 2001. “First-person Reference, Representational Independence, and Self-Knowledge.” In Self-reference and Self-Awareness, edited by A. Brook, and R. C. DeVidi, 215–246. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • Perry, J. 1986. “Thought Without Representation.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 60: 137–151. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/60.1.137.
  • Phillips, I. 2013. “Hearing and Hallucinating Silence.” In Hallucination. Philosophy and Psychology, edited by F. Macpherson, and D. Platchias, 333–359. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Pitron, V., A. Alsmith, and F. de Vignemont. 2018. “How Do the Body Schema and the Body Image Interact?” Consciousness and Cognition 65: 352–358. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2018.08.007.
  • Proske, U., and S. C. Gandevia. 2012. “The Proprioceptive Senses: Their Roles in Signaling Body Shape, Body Position and Movement, and Muscle Force.” Physiological Review 92: 1651–1697. doi:10.1152/physrev.00048.2011.
  • Recanati, F. 2012. “Immunity to Error Through Misidentification: What it is and Where it Comes from.” In Immunity to Error Through Misidentification: New Essays, edited by S. Prosser, and F. Recanati, 180–201. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Richardson, L. 2014. “Non Sense-Specific Perception and the Distinction Between the Senses.” Res Philosophica 91 (2): 215–239. doi:10.11612/resphil.2014.91.2.4.
  • Richardson, L. 2017. “Sight and the Body.” In The Subject’s Matter: Self-Consciousness and the Body, edited by F. de Vignemont, and A. J. T. Alsmith, 239–262. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  • Schellenberg, S. 2007. “Action and Self-Location in Perception.” Mind; A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy 116 (463): 603–632. doi:10.1093/mind/fzm603.
  • Schwenkler, J. 2014. “Vision, Self-Location, and the Phenomenology of the ‘Point of View’.” Noús 48 (1): 137–155. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2012.00871.x.
  • Schwitzgebel, E. 2006. “Do Things Look Flat?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (3): 589–599. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00585.x.
  • Schwoebel, J., and H. B. Coslett. 2005. “Evidence for Multiple, Distinct Representations of the Human Body.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 17 (4): 543–553. doi:10.1162/0898929053467587.
  • Sebastián, MÁ. 2022. “First-Person Perspective in Experience: Perspectival de se Representation as an Explanation of the Delimitation Problem.” Erkenntnis, doi:10.1007/s10670-022-00564-4.
  • Siegel, S. 2010. Contents of Visual Experience. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Smith, A. D. 2002. The Problem of Perception. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Smith, J. 2014. “Egocentric Space.” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (3): 409–433. doi:10.1080/09672559.2014.913888.
  • Soteriou, M. 2011. “The Perception of Absence, Space, and Time.” In Perception, Causation, and Objectivity, edited by J. Roessler, H. Lerman, and N. Eilan, 181–206. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Thompson, E. 2005. “Sensorimotor Subjectivity and the Enactive Approach to Experience.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4: 407–427. doi:10.1007/s11097-005-9003-x.
  • Weksler, A. 2016. “Retinal Images and Object Files: Towards Empirically Evaluating Philosophical Accounts of Visual Perspective.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7: 91–103. doi:10.1007/s13164-015-0239-2.
  • Wexler, M., F. Panerai, I. Lamouret, and J. Droulez. 2001. “Self-motion and the Perception of Stationary Objects.” Nature 409: 85–88. doi:10.1038/35051081.
  • Wong, H. Y. 2015. “On the Significance of Bodily Awareness for Bodily Action.” The Philosophical Quarterly 65 (261): 790–812. doi:10.1093/pq/pqv007.
  • Wu, W. 2011. “What is Conscious Attention?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (1): 93–120. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00457.x.
  • Wu, W. 2014. “Against Division: Consciousness, Information and the Visual Streams.” Mind & Language 29 (4): 383–406. doi:10.1111/mila.12056.
  • Zahavi, D. 1999. Self-awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.