168
Views
1
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Epistemic presentism

ORCID Icon
Pages 458-478 | Received 10 Jun 2017, Accepted 24 Oct 2017, Published online: 15 Feb 2018

References

  • Audi, R. E. (1994). Dispositional beliefs and dispositions to believe. Noûs, 28(4), 419–434.10.2307/2215473
  • Bjerring, C., & Pedersen, N. (2014). All the (many, many) things we know: Extended knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 24–38.10.1111/phis.2014.24.issue-1
  • Block, N. (1980). Troubles with functionalism. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the philosophy of psychology (pp. 268–305). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (2007). Philosophy of mind and cognition: An introduction. London: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Brandom, R. B. (2008). Between saying and doing: Towards an analytic pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199542871.001.0001
  • Braithwaite, R. B. (1932). The nature of believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 33, 129–146.
  • Carruthers, P. 2016. “Higher-order theories of consciousness.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Fall ed. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/consciousness-higher/
  • Chalmers, D. (1996). Does a rock implement every finite state automaton? Synthese, 108, 309–333.10.1007/BF00413692
  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.
  • Churchland, P. M. (2005). Functionalism at forty: A critical retrospective. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 33–50.10.5840/jphil2005102136
  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Clark, A. (2001). Reasons, robots and the extended mind. Mind and Language, 16, 121–145.10.1111/mila.2001.16.issue-2
  • Clark, A. (2007). Curing cognitive hiccups: A defense of the extended mind. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 163–192.10.5840/jphil2007104426
  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195333213.001.0001
  • Clark, A. (2010). Memento’s revenge: The extended mind, extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 43–65). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/9780262014038.001.0001
  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 10–23.
  • Cohen, L. J. (1989). Belief and acceptance. Mind, 98(391), 367–389.10.1093/mind/XCVIII.391.367
  • David, M., & Warfield, T. (2008). Knowledge-closure and scepticism. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays (pp. 137–188). Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199264933.001.0001
  • Dennett, D. C. (1989). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.
  • Farkas, K. (2012). Two versions of the extended mind thesis. Philosophia, 40, 435–447.10.1007/s11406-011-9355-0
  • Froese, T., Gershenson, C., & Rosenblueth, D. A. (2013). The dynamically extended mind. Retrieved from http://arxiv.org/abs/1305.1958
  • Gertler, B. (2008). Overextending the mind? In B. Gertler & L. Shapiro (Eds.), Arguing about the mind (pp. 196–205). London: Routledge.
  • Greco, J. (2008). The value problem. In D. Pritchard, A. Millar, & A. Haddock (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge: Three investigations (pp. 313–321). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511844645
  • Hawthorne, J. (2005). The case for closure. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 26–43). London: Blackwell.
  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Joos, M. (1968). The English verb: Form and meanings. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
  • Kvanvig, J. (2003). Propositionalism and the perspectival character of justification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(1), 3–18.
  • Lehrer, K. (2015). Theory of knowledge. London: Routledge.
  • Levin, J. 2017. “Functionalism.” In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy edited by Edward N. Zalta, Winter ed. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/functionalism/
  • Lynch, D. (2014). ‘Neuromedia, extended knowledge, and understanding. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 299–313.10.1111/phis.2014.24.issue-1
  • Menary, R. (2006). Attacking the bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 19(3), 329–344.10.1080/09515080600690557
  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbound. London: Palgrave McMillan.10.1057/9780230592889
  • Menary, R. (2010). Introduction: The extended mind in focus. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 1–28). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/9780262014038.001.0001
  • Minsky, M. (1985). The society of mind. New York, NY: Simon & Schuster.
  • Mourelatos, A. (1978). Events, processes, and states. Linguistics and Philosophy, 2, 415–434.10.1007/BF00149015
  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Palermos, S. O. (2011). Belief-forming processes, extended. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(4), 741–765.
  • Palermos, S. O., & Pritchard, D. (2013). Extended knowledge and social-epistemology. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective., 2(8), 105–120.
  • Palermos, S. O. (2014a). Loops, constitution, and cognitive extension. Cognitive Systems Research., 27, 25–41.
  • Palermos, S. O. (2014b). Knowledge and cognitive integration. Synthese., 191(8), 1931–1951.
  • Palermos, S. O. (2015). Active externalism, virtue reliabilism and scientific knowledge. Synthese., 192, 29–55.
  • Palermos, S. O. (2016a). Spreading the credit: Virtue reliabilism and weak epistemic anti-individualism. Erkenntnis., 81(2), 305–334.
  • Palermos, S. O. (2016b). The dynamics of group cognition. Minds and Machines., 26(4), 409–440.
  • Poston, T. (2007). Internalism and externalism in epistemology. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://www.iep.utm.edu/int-ext/
  • Pritchard, D. H. (2010a). Cognitive ability and the extended cognition thesis. Synthese, 175, 133–151.10.1007/s11229-010-9738-y
  • Pritchard, D. H. (2010b). Knowledge and understanding. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. H. Pritchard (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge: Three investigations (pp. 315–327). Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199586264.001.0001
  • Pritchard, D. (2016). Epistemic angst: Radical skepticism and the groundlessness of our believing. Princeton: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9781400873913
  • Ramsey, W. 2016. “Eliminative materialism.” In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Winter ed. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/materialism-eliminative/
  • Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Understanding cognitive processes. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511583261
  • Rowlands, M. (2009). Extended cognition and the mark of the cognitive. Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 1–19.10.1080/09515080802703620
  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101, 389–428.10.5840/jphil2004101826
  • Sousa, De (1971). How to give a piece of your mind. Review of Metaphysics, 25(1), 52–79.
  • Sprevak, M. (2009). Extended cognition and functionalism. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 503–527.10.5840/jphil2009106937
  • Stevenson, L. (2002). Six levels of mentality. Philosophical Explorations, 5(2), 105–124.10.1080/10002002058538725
  • Sutton, J., Barnier, A., Harris, C., & Wilson, R. (2008). A conceptual and empirical framework for the social distribution of cognition: The case of memory. Cognitive Systems Research, 9(1–2), 33–51.
  • Swain, M. (1979). Justification and the basis of belief. In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 25–49). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  • Theiner, G. (2011). Res cogitans extensa: A philosophical defense of the extended mind thesis. Bern: Peter Lang GmbH, Europaischer Verlag der Wissenschaften.
  • Theiner, G., Allen, C., & Goldstone, R. (2010). Recognizing group cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 11(4), 378–395.10.1016/j.cogsys.2010.07.002
  • Tollefsen, D., & Dale, R. (2011). Naturalizing joint action: A process-based approach. Philosophical Psychology, 25, 385–407.
  • Turri, J. (2010). On the relation between proposition and doxastic justification. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(2), 312–326.10.1111/phpr.2010.80.issue-2
  • Weiskopf, D. (2008). Patrolling the mind’s boundaries. Erkenntnis, 68, 265–276.10.1007/s10670-007-9095-5
  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Wikforss, Å. (2014). Extended belief and extended knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 460–481.10.1111/phis.2014.24.issue-1
  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wilson, R. A. (2000). The mind beyond itself. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresentations: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 31–52). New York, NY: New York University Press.
  • Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences: Cognition. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.