399
Views
6
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Towards a New Kind of Semantic Normativity

References

  • Blackburn, S. (1984) ‘The Individual Strikes Back’, Synthese 58: 281–301.
  • Boghossian, P. (2005) ‘Is Meaning Normative?’, in A. Beckermann and C. Nimtz (eds) Philosophy – Science – Scientific Philosophy, Paderborn: Mentis.
  • Gampel, E.H. (1997) ‘The Normativity of Meaning’, Philosophical Studies 86: 221–42.
  • Ginsborg, H. (2010) ‘Review of Hattiangadi, A., Oughts and Thoughts: Rule-Following and the Normativity of Content’, Mind 119: 1175–86.
  • Ginsborg, H.. (2011a) ‘Primitive Normativity and Skepticism about Rules’, The Journal of Philosophy 108: 227–54.
  • Ginsborg, H.. (2011b) ‘Inside and Outside Language: Stroud’s Nonreductionism about Meaning’, in J. Bridges, N. Kolodny and W. Wong (eds) The Possibility of Philosophical Understanding: Essays for Barry Stroud, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ginsborg, H.. (2012) ‘‘Meaning, Understanding and Normativity’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86: 127–46.
  • Glüer, K., and Å. Wikforss (2009) ‘Against Content Normativity’, Mind 118: 31–70.
  • Glüer, K., and Å. Wikforss. (2010) The Normativity of Meaning and Content. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/meaning-normativity/>.
  • Haddock, A. (2012) ‘Meaning, Justification, and “Primitive Normativity”’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86: 147–74.
  • Hattiangadi, A. (2006) ‘Is Meaning Normative?’, Mind and Language 21: 220–40.
  • Hattiangadi, A.. (2009) ‘Some More Thoughts on Semantic Oughts: A Reply to Daniel Whiting’, Analysis 69: 54–63.
  • Kripke, S. (1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • McDowell, J. (1984) ‘Wittgenstein on Following a Rule’, Synthese 58: 325–63.
  • McDowell, J.. (1987) ‘In Defence of Modesty’, reprinted in Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Millikan, R. (1984) ‘Truth Rules, Hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein Paradox’, The Philosophical Review 99: 323–53.
  • Stroud, B. (2010) Meaning, Understanding, and Practice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stroud, B.. (2012) ‘Meaning and Understanding’, in J. Ellis and D. Guevara (eds) Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Verheggen, C. (2011) ‘Semantic Normativity and Naturalism’, Logique et Analyse 216: 552–67.
  • Verheggen, C.. (2013) ‘Triangulation’, in E. Lepore and K. Ludwig (eds) A Companion to Donald Davidson, Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.
  • Whiting, D. (2013) ‘What is the Normativity of Meaning?’, Inquiry, doi:10.1080/0020174X.2013.852132.
  • Wikforss, Å. (2001) ‘Semantic Normativity’, Philosophical Studies 102: 203–26.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958) Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe, New York: Macmillan.

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.