221
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Sharing the costs of fighting justly

ORCID Icon

References

  • Abrahms, M. (2006). Why terrorism does not work. International Security, 31, 42–78.
  • Anon. (2016, August 5–18). Ambush Whacked. Private Eye, 1424, 37.
  • Barry, C., & Valentini, L. (2009). Egalitarian challenges to global egalitarianism: A critique. Review of International Studies, 35, 485–512.
  • Bellamy, A. J. (2004). Supreme emergencies and the protection of non-combatants in war. International Affairs, 80, 829–850.
  • Benbaji, Y. (2009). The war convention and the moral division of labour. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59, 593–617.
  • Caney, S. (2015). Responding to global injustice: On the right of resistance. Social Philosophy & Policy, 32, 51–73.
  • Crawford, N. C. (2007). Individual and collective moral responsibility for systemic military atrocity. Journal of Political Philosophy, 15, 187–212.
  • Crawford, N. C. (2013). Accountability for killing: Moral responsibility for collateral damage in America’s post-9/11 wars. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Delmas, C. (2014). Political resistance: A matter of fairness. Law and Philosophy, 33, 465–488.
  • Fabre, C. (2009). Guns, food, and liability to attack in war. Ethics, 120, 36–63.
  • Finlay, C. (2015). Terrorism and the right to resist: A theory of just revolutionary war. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Frowe, H. (2014). Defensive Killing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Horowitz, M., & Reiter, D. (2001). When does aerial bombing work?: Quantitative empirical tests, 1917–1999. The Journal of Conflict Resolution, 45, 147–173.
  • ICRC. (1977). Protocol additional to the Geneva conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the protection of victims of international armed conflicts. Retrieved from https://www.icrc.org/eng/assets/files/other/icrc_002_0321.pdf.
  • ICRC. (n. d.). Declaration renouncing the use, in time of war, of explosive projectiles under 400 grammes weight. Retrieved from https://ihl-databases.icrc.org/ihl/INTRO/130?OpenDocument
  • Jubb, R. (2014). Participation in and responsibility for State injustices. Social Theory and Practice, 40, 51–72.
  • Kalyvas, S. N. (2004). The paradox of terrorism in civil war. The Journal of Ethics, 8, 97–138.
  • Klosko, G. (1987). Presumptive benefit, fairness, and political obligation. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 16, 241–259.
  • Lazar, S. (2012). Necessity in self-defense and war. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 40, 3–44.
  • Lee, S. (2004). Double effect, double intention, and asymmetric warfare. Journal of Military Ethics, 3, 233–251.
  • Lefkowitz, D. (2004). The nature of fairness and political obligation: A response to carr. Social Theory and Practice, 30, 1–31.
  • Lefkowitz, D. (2011). The principle of fairness and States’ duty to obey international law. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, 24, 327–346.
  • Luban, D. (2014). Risk taking and force protection. In Y. Benbaji & N. Sussman (Eds.), Reading walzer (pp. 277–301). London: Routledge.
  • Lyall, J. (2009). Does indiscriminate violence incite insurgent attacks?: Evidence from Chechnya. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 53, 331–362.
  • McMahan, J. (2008). The morality of war and the law of war. In D. Rodin & H. Shue (Eds.), Just and unjust warriors (pp. 19–43). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • McMahan, J. (2009). Killing In War. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Miller, D. (2007). National responsibility and global justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Parsons, S. D. (2005). Fair-play obligations: A critical note on free riding. Political Studies, 53, 641–649.
  • Pasternak, A. (2013). Limiting States’ Corporate Responsibility. Journal of Political Philosophy, 21, 361–381.
  • Rawls, J. (1999). A Theory of Justice (Revised ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Reeves, A. R. (2014). The Binding Force of Nascent Norms of International Law. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, 27, 145–166.
  • Robillard, M., & Strawser, B. J. (2016). The moral exploitation of soldiers. Public Affairs Quarterly, 30, 171–195.
  • Rodin, D. (2002). War and self defense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Sangiovanni, A. (2007). Global justice, reciprocity, and the state. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35, 3–39.
  • Schwenkenbecher, A. (2014). Collateral damage and the principle of due care. Journal of Military Ethics, 13, 94–105.
  • Segall, S. (2005). Unconditional welfare benefits and the principle of reciprocity. Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 4(2), 331–354.
  • Simmons, A. J. (1979). Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Stilz, A. (2011). Collective responsibility and the State. Journal of Political Philosophy, 19(2), 190–208.
  • Walzer, M. (2006). Just and unjust wars (4th ed.). New York: Basic Books.
  • Worley, W. (2016, November 25). Royal Navy’s £1bn warship needs tow home after just two days at sea. The Independent. Retrieved February 21, 2017, from http://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/royal-navy-warship-hms-duncan-tow-plymouth-military-defence-a7438646.html

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.