Publication Cover
Accountability in Research
Ethics, Integrity and Policy
Volume 30, 2023 - Issue 6
4,449
Views
5
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Research Article

Nonfinancial conflict of interest in peer-review: Some notes for discussion

ORCID Icon

ABSTRACT

Strong beliefs can influence the way we deal with emotionally charged topics. Researchers, editors, and reviewers are not an exception. Declaring such nonfinancial conflict of interest when handling or reviewing submitted articles is often obligatory; however, the declaration is not a license to submit a biased review with personal insults or to break the journal’s guidelines. This kind of poor practice can be a clear sign of the seriousness of conflict of interest. In this article, I argue that hostile, unethical, and biased behavior of reviewers and editors often arises from a serious nonfinancial conflict of interest, which should not be ignored or undermined.

Introduction

During the last decade, there has been an extensive discussion about nonfinancial conflicts of interest (COI) in science. Some argue that nonfinancial interests do not constitute a COI (Bero and Grundy Citation2016) while others emphasize the dangers of neglecting them (Wiersma, Kerridge, and Lipworth Citation2018a).

On one side of the debate, nonfinancial COIs are considered too complex and difficult to detect and manage; less damaging than financial COIs; of lower ethical priority compared with financial COI; represent a red herring for financial COIs. It is further argued that as no one is fully neutral and free of biases, anything and everything can potentially be labeled a COI; not all intellectual interests represent a COI; a diversity of perspectives is needed for the advancement of science; and disclosure of some interests may raise ethical and privacy concerns (Bero Citation2017; Bero and Grundy Citation2016; Goldberg Citation2020; Rodwin Citation2018; Wiersma, Kerridge, and Lipworth Citation2018a, Citation2018b).

According to the other view, “dismissing nonfinancial COIs is naive, empirically unfounded, and dangerous” (Wiersma, Kerridge, and Lipworth Citation2018b, 1). Both grant applicants and reviewers are concerned about nonfinancial COIs (Abdoul et al. Citation2012), although there is no consensus among experts in the field about what constitutes a nonfinancial COI (Grundy et al. Citation2020). A vast literature on cognitive biases provides enough evidence to justify concerns that strong beliefs, values, etc. can interfere with our work as scientists. If we exclude fabrication, p-hacking, HARKing, and the file-drawer effect, which are difficult to discover, the work of authors can be largely scrutinized in the context of their COI as their published work, public appearances, and their names are publicly known (Bero Citation2017; Rodwin Citation2018). On the other hand, it is much more difficult to detect a COI among peer-reviewers and address them transparently or publicly ().

Table 1. Detectability of COIs among authors, editors, and reviewers.

In this commentary, I focus on nonfinancial COI among journal editors and peer-reviewers. I base my discussion on my experiences and observations as an author, peer reviewer, and associate editor in the field of traffic safety. This is an applied discipline, which research findings have direct influence on policy making. Consequently, debates often go beyond academics and involve various stakeholders and parties with different interests.

For example, issues related to bicycle helmets are among the most controversial in traffic safety research (Goldacre and Spiegelhalter Citation2013; Olivier et al. Citation2014). Although biomedical (Cripton et al. Citation2014; McIntosh, Lai, and Schilter Citation2013), computer simulation (Fahlstedt, Halldin, and Kleiven Citation2016; McNally and Whitehead Citation2013), and case-control studies (Høye Citation2018; Olivier and Creighton Citation2017) show bicycle helmets’ efficacy and effectiveness in mitigating head injuries, many are skeptical, pointing out their limitations in crashes occurring at higher speeds and those involving motor vehicles. Furthermore, some (e.g., Adams and Hillman Citation2001) have proposed that wearing a helmet increases the risk of being involved in a crash because of risk compensation (i.e., helmet wearing-> feeling safer->taking more risks->crash more likely). Others are concerned that promotion and legislation of helmets leads to less cycling (Robinson Citation1998, Citation2003), which is a healthy activity (Mueller et al. Citation2015; Oja et al. Citation2011), and that less cycling would reduce the overall health benefits on a population level.

Heated debates on any of these issues are frequent especially on social media, where researches perceived as pro-helmet are often accused of producing fraudulent research, working for the benefit of the car industry, or, in the best case, only mocked for wasting resources on an unimportant issue such as bicycle helmets. Personal insults are common. This is nothing unusual for “debates” on social media (Kelland Citation2019). More problematic is when strong personal interests interfere with the desired objectivity of peer-review process.

Strong personal beliefs as a conflict of interest

Strong personal beliefs are often mentioned as a potential nonfinancial conflict of interest regarding “emotionally charged topics” such as human stem cells, abortion, evolution, gun control, marriage laws, etc. (Grundy et al. Citation2020; Rockwell Citation2006). Bicycle helmets, as one of the most controversial issues in traffic safety research, clearly fall within this category.

A well-known and respected active travel researcher said in a recent interview “I have been a hater of cars from my entire life. And that was what I was actually motivated my entire academic career” (Bernstein, & Reid, Citation2021, 2:49). Although the negative impact of cars on the environment and health is well researched and documented, it can hardly be put in the same category as cancer for example. There is a broad scientific consensus that no benefits can be associated with cancer, thus, hating cancer seems appropriate, although such researchers should be conscious about their strong motivation and the negative effects it can have on their work (e.g., observer bias). The same can hardly be said about cars as a machine. Openly stating that hate toward cars preceded and motivated an entire academic career is a clear sign of a biased approach to the topic of one’s research. A legitimate question arises here: if you hate the topic of your research, be it a car or perhaps a bicycle helmet, how will you as an editor or reviewer deal with a paper that says anything positive about cars or helmets?

Participation in heated scientific debates as a conflict of interest

Participation in heated scientific debates has also been mentioned as a possible source of conflict of interest (Rockwell Citation2006). The reason for this participation might be related to strong personal beliefs, including hate, as discussed previously, but it can simply be related to the researcher’s work in general or even to specific article(s).

An interesting situation concerns journals’ treatment of commentaries that focus on a particular paper. Some journals do not peer review commentaries, while others treat them in the same way they would the submission of a research paper. Inviting the authors of the target article to review a commentary might seem logical because these authors are experts and obviously highly motivated to provide a detailed assessment of the commentary. However, the inviting editor must be mindful of their biased perspective and carefully evaluate their peer review. If such reviews contain personal insults or question the authors’ motivation, they should always be discarded because they are clear signs of a serious COI. Journals have several different ways of handling such submissions:

* EiC accepts/rejects a commentary without peer review, and invites the authors of the target article to respond after possible acceptance

* EiC invites the authors of the target article to respond, and then makes a decision whether they will publish together both commentary and response

* EiC sends a commentary to an external peer review and after possible acceptance invites the authors of the target article to respond

* In addition to external reviewers, EiC includes the authors of the target article as peer reviewers and based on their review (not a formal response) makes a decision on the submitted commentary.

All of these approaches have pros and cons; however, it is of the utmost importance that the journal’s guidelines should be clear about the procedure especially if the authors of the target articles are routinely invited to provide a peer review of a commentary. A recent COPE document offers some guidelines about “handling of post-publication critiques” (COPE Council Citation2021).

Who is qualified to be a peer reviewer? Personal interests are not the proof of expertise

A reviewer should be an expert in the research field with at least some “proof” of having enough specialist knowledge needed to evaluate a manuscript. The proof is a reasonable publication record in the research field. In one of my recent submissions, the journal invited a non-researcher and the founder of a cycling advocacy group to review our paper in which, among other issues, we exposed this reviewer’s careless citation of an alleged finding from a secondary source. One could argue whether the single publication (a blog text) that this reviewer had constitutes a good enough proof of the required specialist knowledge.

Recruiting peer reviewers has been increasingly difficult in recent years in some journals (e.g., Fox, Albert, and Vines Citation2017), so it is possible that even the best journals sometimes adopt the take-what-you-can-get strategy. Unfortunately, the most motivated and willing reviewers could well be those who might benefit if a paper remains unpublished. The editors should be mindful of this possibility especially if the tone or content of the review supports it. The purpose of peer-review is not to ”kill the paper,” but to evaluate it in terms of its strengths and limitations.

Who can be an editor? Conflicts of commitments

Here I offer an example from my field of research regarding the connecting between the Journal of Transport and Health (JTH) and the organization called Transport and Health Study Group – THSG, which among other goals aims “To promote a more balanced approach to cycle safety and oppose cycle helmet legislation” [my underline]. Given that the journal’s EiC and several editorial board members belonged also to THSG, concerns about JTH’s editorial decisions being influenced by THSG’s goals were expressed in a blog post. It asked “ … will a paper that says anything positive about helmets or helmet legislation (backed by evidence) be peer-reviewed without this goal influencing the decision to publish? Also, will authors shy away from citing peer-reviewed articles that demonstrate evidence supportive of helmets or helmet laws?” (Olivier Citation2014)

In a public discussion the EiC replied: “In summary, many journals are associated with organizations but the society does not influence the journal. The BMJ does not take note of BMA policy” (Mindell Citation2014). However, this has provoked the following response (Churches Citation2014): “Yes, it is true that the British Medical Association has policies, and no, those policies don’t affect the editorial policies or decisions of the British Medical Journal, which the BMA publishes. But a key difference is that office bearers and policy-makers in the BMA are NOT the same people as the editors and editorial staff of the BMJ.”

The loyalty to one’s own advocacy group and own journal (i.e., science) might sometimes be in conflict. This is what is usually called “conflicts of commitments” (Wiersma, Kerridge, and Lipworth Citation2018a). To somewhat exaggerate this, imagine an EiC who belongs to an organization that is against gun control and promises they will treat equally submissions that are perceived as supportive or opposed to gun control. It is extremely difficult to prove that editors chose reviewers they knew would be negative (or positive) toward a particular paper or that someone’s bias has led to an unfair peer review; however, offensive language and knowingly violating journal rules should be taken very seriously if there is also another reason (e.g., belonging to an advocacy group) for suspecting serious bias.

How should publishers deal with official complaints – are nonfinancial COIs of secondary importance?

As Dalton (Citation2001, 103) writes “ … it is often difficult to distinguish between genuine complaints and paranoia. Many editors can relate tales of anguished authors convinced that a reviewer had abused the process.” However, if a complaint contains evidence of a serious breach of journal guidelines (e.g., knowingly violating the journal’s double-blind policy), publishers should respond formally.

Some may argue the case of knowingly breaching the journal’s privacy rule is a minor or even an irrelevant matter considering how difficult it is to get an adequate response from publishers in more serious cases of “plagiarism, image, data, or ethical concerns” (Bik Citation2020). It is indeed possible that publishers give greater priority to more serious cases due to time constraints and simply ignore those perceived as minor. On the other hand, the way of communication can sometimes be perceived as unduly aggressive or unprofessional, leading to a label of a “difficult author” who can be ignored (see Smart Citation2020 for a discussion about difficult authors).

Small research fields and nonfinancial COIs

Bero and Grundy (Citation2016, 4) assert that, “ … while personal relationships can lead to conflicts of interest, unlike conflicts of interest arising from financial ties, their effects rarely extend beyond the immediate situation.” However, this might not be true when a research field is small and narrow with a limited number of highly respected researchers who might shape the field both through their research work and also as peer-reviewers or editors. For example, one of my bicycle helmet papers was recently reviewed by the same reviewer for two journals indicating that the research field is indeed small. As someone who has extensively published on the topic of driver fatigue, I was also invited to review the same paper for two different journals. In small research fields, it is of the utmost importance to have a diverse editorial board, change EiCs in reasonable time frames, and perhaps not to select them from the same advocacy group.

The current “About the journal” section of mentioned JTH includes no information about the connection between the journal and THSG. The current EiC has also failed to mention he is on the board of THSG (EiC’s biography Citationn.d.). However, on their website THSG states that “The THSG works with: The Journal of Transport and Health” (THSG Citationn.d.). It is, therefore, unclear what the exact relationship between two is. Does, for example, THSG nominate EiCs and the publisher only approves them or does THSG have no influence other than through members who have dual roles both in the group and the journal? It is unclear why this relationship is not transparently described on the journal’s webpage.

Is transparency the key for nonfinancial COIs?

In a recent addendum, the editors of The Lancet (Citation2021) wrote: “In line with guidance from the International Committee of Medical Journal Editors, medical journals ask authors to report financial and non-financial relationships that may be relevant to interpreting the content of their manuscript. There may be differences in opinion as to what constitutes a competing interest. Transparent reporting allows readers to make judgments about these interests.” However, readers can make such judgments only if a manuscript is published and only for the authors if the names of the handling editor and reviewers are not made public (). Furthermore, if reviewers do not sign their reviews, then it is impossible for authors to detect the possible peer-reviewers’ COIs and report them to editors. In a study examining COIs among grant reviewers for the American Institute of Biological Sciences, it was found that 35% of identified conflicts were self-reported, while 65% were identified by the institute staff (Gallo, Lemaster, and Glisson Citation2016).

How to recognize undeclared COI or seriousness of declared COI?

The problem of hostile and unprofessional reviews/reviewers has long been recognized (Lanier Citation2021; Resnik and Elmore Citation2016; Silbiger and Stubler Citation2019). The reasons for such behavior are naturally multiple and complex. Some reviewers might fail to spot their own unintended inappropriate language due to lack of time and pressure to comply with deadlines. Poor language and communication skills as well as cultural differences might produce unforeseen interpretations. Various personality traits such as aggressiveness, narcissism, and lack of self-awareness may also play a role.

However, I argue that the hostile, unethical, and biased behavior of reviewers and editors often arises from a serious nonfinancial COI, which then remains unrecognized or even ignored despite clear evidence of biased behavior. For example, using an editorial to mock your “opponents”; preventing these “opponents” from responding to this incorrect information; knowingly ignoring the journal’s guidelines; accepting peer-reviews with insults and questioning others’ motivation for writing their papers are all potential signs of serious COI. Even if nonfinancial COIs are self-reported, the declaration is not a license to submit a biased review with personal insults or to break the journal’s guidelines.

How to manage non-financial COI?

Bero and Grundy (Citation2016, 3) argue that “if the only solution for a particular type of interest is recusal because the interest cannot be eliminated, this is not a conflict of interest but rather part of the researcher’s professional role or personal identity.” This is perhaps too strict a rule that does not take into account that the benefit-to-cost ratio of a recusal will be high and will not vary significantly across different roles which have power (). For example, declining to review a manuscript because of a non-financial COI (which does not have to be specified) will hardly produce any harm to a researcher (invitations to review are declined on a daily basis), while the benefit might be considerable. Even if a research field is small, there will be other qualified persons willing to perform the reviewing task. The same applies to grant reviewers. Similarly, all journals should already have in place a procedure to transfer manuscripts to other editors, so the difficulty of editors exempting themselves from dealing with certain submissions will be negligible. A problem, however, might arise if there is no diversity among editorial board members (e.g., if most belong to the same advocacy group).

This kind of pragmatic approach (low cost, high benefit) can easily be applied to those involved in peer-review. For authors, the situation might be somewhat more complicated as they must obviously be more specific about any interests that can cloud their objectivity than a reviewer who declines to review a specific paper. Further problems might arise if a journal uses a double-blind peer review where providing details about personal interests might reveal an author’s identity. Nevertheless, as mentioned previously, once a paper has been published, it can be scrutinized in the context of the authors’ overall activities, which are publicly known.

The main problem with non-financial COI, as stated in this paper, concerns those who have power in the peer-review process. The system that relies on the peer-reviewers’ honesty or their understanding of what constitutes a COI might not be fully efficient especially if the authors and larger academic audience do not even know about peer-reviewers’ identity. Furthermore, it is well known that most of the journals’ guidelines and rules regarding COI apply to authors and not to editors and reviewers (Resnik, Konecny, and Kissling Citation2017). Several major journals have recently “tightened rules on non-financial conflicts” (Nature editorial Citation2018) and require that all involved (authors, reviewers and editors) must declare possible competing interests (Nature Citationn.d.). Whether this will improve the peer-review process remains to be seen.

Concluding remarks

In a situation where prestigious journals have a less than 10% acceptance rate, it is very unlikely that a paper without highly supportive reviews will be accepted. Reviews submitted by researchers or non-researchers with a serious (nonfinancial) conflict of interest are never going to be “highly supportive.” It is also unlikely that editors who hate a certain research topic or have conflict of commitments will be free of bias when selecting potential reviewers of papers perceived to be in conflict with their strong attitudes or goals of their advocacy group. In conclusion, ignoring or downplaying the nonfinancial COI of editors and peer-reviewers, especially regarding controversial issues in small research fields, is indeed dangerous and harmful to the scholarly community.

Disclosure statement

The author has been involved in a dispute with the editors of the mentioned Journal of Transport and Health regarding two of his submissions to this journal on the controversial topic of bicycle helmets. The present work has not received any direct funding. However, the author’s current projects (Road traffic suicides and Road user identities) are supported by several organizations, including the Automobile and Touring Club of Finland (ATCF), the Finnish Crash Data Institute (OTI), the Henry Ford foundation, Katsastustoiminnan Tukisäätiö, Kuorma-autoliikenteen Volvo Säätiö, Liikenneturva, Liikenneturvallisuuden Edistämissäätiö, Rahtarit, Liikennelääketieteen säätiö, and the Transport Workers’ Union AKT. Given that anti-helmet (law) advocates often claim that perceived pro-helmet researchers work for the benefit of the car industry, this funding might be perceived as COI.

Additional information

Funding

The author(s) reported there is no funding associated with the work featured in this article.

References

  • Abdoul, H., C. Perrey, F. Tubach, P. Amiel, I. Durand-Zaleski, and C. Alberti. 2012. “Non-Financial Conflicts of Interest in Academic Grant Evaluation: A Qualitative Study of Multiple Stakeholders in France”. PLoS ONE 7: e35247. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0035247.
  • Adams, J., and M. Hillman. 2001. “The Risk Compensation Theory and Bicycle Helmets.” Injury Prevention 7: 89–91. doi:10.1136/ip.7.2.89.
  • Bernstein, D., and C. Reid (Hosts). 2021. “Ralph Buehler and John Pucher on Cycling for Sustainable Cities (No. 273) [Audio Podcast].” Spokesmen cycling Podcast, May 8. Accessed 24 September 2021. https://www.the-spokesmen.com/cyclingforsustainablecities/
  • Bero, L. A. 2017. “Addressing Bias and Conflict of Interest among Biomedical Researchers.” JAMA 317: 1723–1724. doi:10.1001/jama.2017.3854.
  • Bero, L. A., and Q. Grundy. 2016. “Why Having a (Nonfinancial) Interest Is Not a Conflict of Interest.” PLoS Biology 14: e2001221. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.2001221.
  • Bik, E. 2020, December 31. “2020: A Year in Review.” Accessed 24 September 2021. https://scienceintegritydigest.com/2020/12/31/2020-a-year-in-review/
  • Churches, T. 2014. “Journal of Transport and Health and Publication Bias?” Accessed 24 September 2021. https://injurystats.wordpress.com/2014/03/28/jth-bias/
  • COPE Council. 2021. COPE Flowcharts and Infographics — Handling of Post-publication Critiques — English. doi:10.24318/o1VgCAih.
  • Cripton, P. A., D. M. Dressler, C. A. Stuart, C. R. Dennison, and D. Richards. 2014. “Bicycle Helmets are Highly Effective at Preventing Head Injury during Head Impact: Head-form Accelerations and Injury Criteria for Helmeted and Unhelmeted Impacts.” Accident Analysis and Prevention 70: 1–7. doi:10.1016/j.aap.2014.02.016.
  • Dalton, R. 2001. “Peers under Pressure.” Nature 413 (6852): 102–104. doi:10.1038/35093252.
  • EiC’s biography. n.d. Accessed 24 September 2021. https://www.journals.elsevier.com/journal-of-transport-and-health/editorial-board/charles-ba-musselwhite-phd-pgcert-distinction-bsc-hons
  • Fahlstedt, M., P. Halldin, and S. Kleiven. 2016. “The Protective Effect of a Helmet in Three Bicycle Accidents—a Finite Element Study.” Accident Analysis and Prevention 91: 135–143. doi:10.1016/j.aap.2016.02.025.
  • Fox, C. W., A. Y. Albert, and T. H. Vines. 2017. “Recruitment of Reviewers is Becoming Harder at Some Journals: A Test of the Influence of Reviewer Fatigue at Six Journals in Ecology and Evolution.” Research Integrity and Peer Review 2 (1): 3. doi:10.1186/s41073-017-0027-x.
  • Gallo, S. A., M. Lemaster, and S. R. Glisson. 2016. “Frequency and Type of Conflicts of Interest in the Peer Review of Basic Biomedical Research Funding Applications: Self-Reporting versus Manual Detection.” Science and Engineering Ethics 22: 189–197. doi:10.1007/s11948-015-9631-7.
  • Goldacre, B., and D. Spiegelhalter. 2013. “Bicycle Helmets and the Law.” BMJ 346: f3817. doi:10.1136/bmj.f3817.
  • Goldberg, D. S. 2020. “Financial Conflicts of Interest are of Higher Ethical Priority than “Intellectual” Conflicts of Interest.” Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 17: 217–227. doi:10.1007/s11673-020-09989-4.
  • Grundy, Q., C. Mayes, K. Holloway, S. Mazzarello, B. D. Thombs, and L. Bero. 2020. “Conflict of Interest as Ethical Shorthand: Understanding the Range and Nature of “Non-financial Conflict of Interest” in Biomedicine.” Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 120: 1–7. doi:10.1016/j.jclinepi.2019.12.014.
  • Høye, A. 2018. “Bicycle Helmets–to Wear or Not to Wear? A Meta-analyses of the Effects of Bicycle Helmets on Injuries.” Accident Analysis and Prevention 117: 85–97. doi:10.1016/j.aap.2018.03.026.
  • Kelland, K. 2019. “Special Report: Online Activists are Silencing Us, Scientists Say.” Reuters, March 13. Accessed 24 September 2021. https://www.reuters.com/article/us-science-social-media-specialreport/special-report-online-activists-are-silencing-us-scientists-say-idUSKBN1QU1EI
  • Lanier, W. L. 2021. “Dealing with Inappropriate-, Low-quality-, and Other Forms of Challenging Peer Review, Including Hostile Referees and Inflammatory or Confusing Critiques: Prevention and Treatment.” Accountability in Research: Policies and Quality Assurance 21: 162–185. doi:10.1080/08989621.2020.1815010.
  • McIntosh, A. S., A. Lai, and E. Schilter. 2013. “Bicycle Helmets: Head Impact Dynamics in Helmeted and Unhelmeted Oblique Impact Tests.” Traffic Injury Prevention 14: 501–508. doi:10.1080/15389588.2012.727217.
  • McNally, D. S., and S. Whitehead. 2013. “A Computational Simulation Study of the Influence of Helmet Wearing on Head Injury Risk in Adult Cyclists.” Accident Analysis and Prevention 60: 15–23. doi:10.1016/j.aap.2013.07.011.
  • Mindell, J. 2014. “Journal of Transport and Health and Publication Bias?” August 22. Accessed 24 September 2021. https://injurystats.wordpress.com/2014/03/28/jth-bias/
  • Mueller, N., D. Rojas-Rueda, T. Cole-Hunter, A. De Nazelle, E. Dons, R. Gerike, T. Götschi, L. Int Panis, S. Kahlmeier, and M. Nieuwenhuijsen. 2015. “Health Impact Assessment of Active Transportation: A Systematic Review.” Preventive Medicine 76: 103–114. doi:10.1016/j.ypmed.2015.04.010.
  • Nature. n.d. “Competing Interests.” Accessed 24 September 2021 https://www.nature.com/nature-portfolio/editorial-policies/competing-interests
  • Nature editorial. 2018. “Nature Journals Tighten Rules on Non-financial Conflicts.” Nature 554: 6. doi:10.1038/d41586-018-01420-8.
  • Of The Lancet, E.; Editors of the Lancet. 2021. “Addendum: Competing Interests and the Origins of SARS-CoV-2.” The Lancet 397: 2449. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(21)01377-5.
  • Oja, P., S. Titze, A. Bauman, B. De Geus, P. Krenn, B. Reger-Nash, and T. Kohlberger. 2011. “Health Benefits of Cycling: A Systematic Review”. Scandinavian Journal of Medicine & Science in Sports 21: 496–509. doi:10.1111/j.1600-0838.2011.01299.x.
  • Olivier, J. 2014. “Journal of Transport and Health and Publication Bias? [Blog Post],” March 14. Accessed 24 September 2021. https://injurystats.wordpress.com/2014/03/28/jth-bias/
  • Olivier, J., J. J. Wang, W. Scott, and R. Grzebieta. 2014. “Anti-helmet Arguments: Lies, Damned Lies and Flawed Statistics.” Journal of the Australasian College of Road Safety 25: 10–23.
  • Olivier, J., and P. Creighton. 2017. “Bicycle Injuries and Helmet Use: A Systematic Review and Meta-analysis.” International Journal of Epidemiology 46: 278–292. doi:10.1093/ije/dyw153.
  • Resnik, D. B., B. Konecny, and G. E. Kissling. 2017. “Conflict of Interest and Funding Disclosure Policies of Environmental, Occupational, and Public Health Journals.” Journal of Occupational and Environmental Medicine 59: 28–33. doi:10.1097/JOM.0000000000000910.
  • Resnik, D. B., and S. A. Elmore. 2016. “Ensuring the Quality, Fairness, and Integrity of Journal Peer Review: A Possible Role of Editors.” Science and Engineering Ethics 22: 169–188. doi:10.1007/s11948-015-9625-5.
  • Robinson, D. L. 1998. “Helmet Laws and Health.” Injury Prevention 4: 170–172. doi:10.1136/ip.4.3.170.
  • Robinson, D. L. 2003. “Helmet Laws and Cycle Use.” Injury Prevention 9: 380–381. doi:10.1136/ip.9.4.380.
  • Rockwell, S. 2006. “Ethics of Peer Review: A Guide for Manuscript Reviewers.” Accessed 28 February 2021. http://ori.hhs.gov/sites/default/files/prethics.pdf
  • Rodwin, M. A. 2018. “Attempts to Redefine Conflicts of Interest.” Accountability in Research 25: 67–78. doi:10.1080/08989621.2017.1405728.
  • Silbiger, N. J., and A. D. Stubler. 2019. “Unprofessional Peer Reviews Disproportionately Harm Underrepresented Groups in STEM.” PeerJ 7: e8247. doi:10.7717/peerj.8247.
  • Smart, P. 2020. “Dealing with Difficult Authors.” European Science Editing 46: e52201. doi:10.3897/ese.2020.e52201.
  • THSG. n.d. “The Transport and Health Science Group.” Accessed 24 September 2021. https://www.transportandhealth.org.uk/
  • Wiersma, M., I. Kerridge, and W. Lipworth. 2018a. “Dangers of Neglecting Non-financial Conflicts of Interest in Health and Medicine.” Journal of Medical Ethics 44: 319–322. doi:10.1136/medethics-2017-104530.
  • Wiersma, M., I. Kerridge, and W. Lipworth. 2018b. “Should We Try to Manage Non-financial Interests?” BMJ 361: k1240. doi:10.1136/bmj.k1240.